Pages

Monday, September 21, 2020

Heidegger, Martin, La fine della filosofia


Heidegger, Martin  La fine della filosofia

La metafisica come storia dell'essere I due bozzetti per una storia dell'essere come metafisica

Heidegger, Martin, 1889 -1.976. La fine della filosofia

tradotto da Giovanna Stambaugh. p. cm. Originariamente pubblicato: New York: Harper & Row, 1973. Include riferimenti bibliografici. ISBN 0-226-32383-8 (carta: alcalino. Carta) 1. Metafisica. 2. Ontologia. I. titolo

INTRODUZIONE di Joan Stambaugh

Questo piccolo volume contiene altamente condensato tentativo più esplicito di Heidegger per mostrare la storia dell'essere come metafisica. Il quarto capitolo, "Il superamento di Metafisica", è tratto dal volume tedesco, Vortrage und Aufsatze

Altri tre capitoli, "La metafisica come storia dell'essere", "Studi per una storia dell'essere come metafisica," e di "raccoglimento in Metafisica," sono prese dalla fine del Volume I1 di Nietzsche. I l resto Nietzsche sarà pubblicato in due volumi, un volume contenente il materiale sul nichilismo e un volume finale contenente il materiale su Nietzsche corretto. Questo libro contiene poco presenti su Nietzsche in quanto tale, ma, piuttosto, rappresenta il frutto di due volumi dal titolo tedesco Nietzsche.

 

E 'pubblicato per primo, perch contiene un trattamento pi completo di Heidegger della storia dell'essere come metafisica, a cominciare da Platone e Aristotele e continuando attraverso Schelling e Kierkegaard. All'inizio di Essere e tempo, Heidegger afferma che intende realizzare due cose: (1) l'interpretazione del Dasein in termini di temporalit e la spiegazione del tempo come orizzonte trascendentale per la questione dell'essere, e (2) un fenomenologica distruzione della storia dell'ontologia. Si potrebbe dire che il presente volume si avvicina il pi nulla Heidegger ha pubblicato a svolgere tale "distruzione". Ma, a parte il fatto che la un po 'fuorviante e ambiguo termine "distruzione" stata oggetto di critiche inadeguate, e pertanto deve essere chiarito, l'intenzione in questo libro per nulla coincide semplicemente con quello espresso in Essere e tempo.

 

 INTRODUZIONE

 

Introduzione

 

I l piano originale per Essere e tempo 'composto di due parti. Da una parte aveva tre divisioni, due delle quali sono stati pubblicati nel volume che: (1) l'analisi preparatoria fondamentale del Dasein, (2) Dasein e temporalit, e, infine, (3) Tempo e Essere, che Heidegger poi effettuati nel forma della parte alect ~ re due, che. ~ portato a compimento la distruzione fenomenologica della storia dell'ontologia con la problematica della temporalit come una guida, allo stesso modo aveva tre divisioni: (dottrina 1) kantiana dello schematismo e del tempo, (2) il fondamento ontologico del cogito Descartes somma ', e (saggio 3) di Aristotele in tempo. Dei tre pensatori di nome, solo a Kant che Heidegger ha dedicato diverse pubblicazioni. Aristotele discusso in alcuni saggi e conferenze; Cartesio una figura centrale in tutto, ma non l'oggetto di una pubblicazione separata. In altre parole, il previsto inizialmente sei divisioni di Essere e tempo, due sono contenuti in quel volume, due sono pi o meno effettuato in pubblicazioni successive separate, e le ultime due sono in gran parte assorbito attraverso scritti di Heidegger. Cos si potrebbe dire che nei suoi lavori pubblicati Heidegger ha eseguito la prima parte della sua impresa filosofica, l'interpretazione del Dasein in termini di temporalit e la spiegazione del tempo come orizzonte trascendentale per la questione dell'essere, nella forma che aveva originariamente previsto per il esso. L a seconda parte, la "distruzione", effettuata da una fondazione filosofica molto diversa da quella inizialmente prevista. Cercher di spiegare come la seconda fondazione si differenzia dal primo, e quindi provare a chiarire il significato di tale nuova base per le relazioni di: (1) Essere esseri (la differenza ontologica) e (2) essenza-esistenza ( la "differenza" o distinzione della metafisica). Si tratta di una interpretazione in cui io sono parzialmente aiutati e guidati da Heidegger risposte ai quesiti su

1. Cf. Essere e tempo, trad. Macquarrie da John e Edward Robinson (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), pp. 63-64. 2. Cf. On Time e l'essere, trad. Stambaugh da Joan (N e w York: Harper & Row,

1972).

 

il soggetto. E 'anche una interpretazione che deve necessariamente rimanere un tentativo incompleto. L 'previsto in origine "distruzione" doveva essere fenomenologico in termini di ermeneutica trascendentale. Queste elementsphenomenology, l'ermeneutica, e philosophyHeidegger trascendentale legati indissolubilmente insieme in Essere e tempo, ed proprio su tutti e tre i cui intende rinunciare al suo pensiero successivo. Cos la distruzione da effettuare non pu pi avere il carattere di questi tre elementi, perch essi stessi fanno la storia di ontologia e sono quindi in alcun modo in grado di "distruggere" o disfare quella storia. La distruzione della storia dell'ontologia deve essere intrapresa in termini di storia della Being3 e deve essere pensato dallo stanziamento. Si deve mettere a nudo il rapporto delle trasformazioni epocali dell'essere allo stanziamento. Qui, come in Essere e tempo, il termine "distruzione" si intende il unbuilding (de-struere) degli strati di coprire la natura originale di essere, gli strati che il pensiero metafisico ha con-figure. Nel suo tentativo di abbandonare l'enfasi che ha posto il pensiero metafisico sul nesso di causalit (l'essere pensato esclusivamente come il fondamento dell'essere), Heidegger, in particolare nel suo pensiero pi tardi, viene sempre pi al centro il rapporto tra identit e differenza. In questo rapporto di fondamentale diference che riceve l'accento primario, dal momento che l'identit non pensato tradizionalmente come statica, equazione di astratto, ma come appartenente-insieme, il che ha senso solo in termini di ci che difers. Per Heidegger, a differire letteralmente a dif-fer, a per-dura, trasportare, detenere, e confermano la relazione tra ci che appartiene insieme. prima formulazione di Heidegger di questo rapporto in Essere e tempo la differenza ontologica, la differenza tra essere ed ente. Questa differenza ontologica, di nome ma non effettuati in Essere e tempo, non mai stato pensato dalla metafisica e dovrebbe essere

3. Cf. p. 1

 

 INTRODUZIONE

 

Introduzione

 

vissuto in un modo nuovo di fuori della metafisica. Cos la differenza ontologica rimane qualcosa di inaccessibile per Heidegger in linea di principio alla metafisica, qualcosa da vivere e trasformata in termini di appropriazione. Che cosa fa la metafisica, che Heidegger definisce come la separazione di essenza ed esistenza, iniziata con Platone, hanno a che fare con la differenza ontologica dell'essere e degli esseri? Si potrebbe dire che la tradizione, in particolare per la tradizione medievale, sarebbe equiparare queste due distinzioni. Essere (esse) l'essenza degli esseri, di ci che esiste (existentia), l'essenza, nel senso di quella universale che unifica tutto. Per Heidegger, l'essenza distinzione-esistenza in realt appartiene alla tradizione dalla parte dell'essere, ma il diference tra l'Essere e gli esseri, anche se costantemente presupposta da ogni metafisica, non mai stato pensato. Solo quando la metafisica raggiunge il suo compimento non sorgere la possibilit di trasformare la differenza ontologica, di pensare che dal presupposto di ogni metafisica impensato torna alla sua origine essenziale per appropriazione. L a maggior parte di questo volume impegnato nella elaborazione di ci che accaduto nella storia dell'essere come metafisica. Con la distinzione di Platone di essenza (whatness) ed esistenza (thatness), la differenza tra essere ed ente oscurata, e in quanto tale pensato esclusivamente in termini della sua relazione con gli esseri come loro causa prima (causa prima, causa sui) e quindi se stessa come la pi alta di quegli esseri (summum ens). Cos la metafisica come storia dell'essere, come la storia delle trasformazioni epocali dell'essere, proprio la storia dell'oblio dell'essere. Quando la distinzione di essenza ed esistenza si pone, l'essenza, whatness, che ha la priorit. L a priorit di essenza sull'esistenza rimanda a un altro accento su esseri. T ha significato originale di esistenza come physis, originario, derivante, rendere presente, si perde, e l'esistenza si pensa solo a differenza di essenza come ci che "di fatto" esiste. In contrasto con ci che "di fatto" esiste qui e ora, l'Essere si configura come presenza stabile, una presenza (nominale) astratti da rendere presente (verbale) in termini di spaziotemporale.

 

Questo volume traccia la storia delle trasformazioni epocali dell'essere fino al pensiero di Heidegger in Essere e tempo, e ricorda che al di l di ci che ha da dire in proposito lo stanziamento. Come egli osserva, la natura essenziale dell'essere pu essere spiegato in termini di appropriazione, ma lo stanziamento pu in alcun modo essere intesa come una forma di "Essere". E 'nello spirito di queste osservazioni circa la metafisica come la storia della oblio dell'essere che il titolo di questo volume di essere compreso. I l fine della filosofia non significa che la filosofia di Heidegger in quanto tale diventata una cosa del passato, una ricerca che ha fatto il suo significato per la natura umana. N Heidegger significa che la filosofia nel suo senso fondamentale ha svolto il suo telos, che il "duro lavoro del concetto" (Hegel) ha compiuto il suo compito. Piuttosto, egli intende che la filosofia come metafisica giunto a una conclusione, che offre ora la possibilit di un modo pi originale di pensare. L a seguito domande e risposte, quali sono aggiunti cerchio attorno al rapporto dell'essere, il tempo, e di appropriazione, nella speranza che possano gettare ulteriore luce su questi problemi ^. ^

1. Temporalit.

 

DOMANDA: al concetto di temporalit, cos accade cenWhat

trale in Essere e tempo, nel tuo pensiero pi tardi? C' un rapporto tra temporalit e appropriazione? RISPOSTA: La temporalit "centrale" in Essere e tempo, perch la questione dell'essere come tale, nel senso di presenza inizia con un analitico dell'essere umano che si tiene estaticamente aperto all'essere. Come conseguenza del turno, la temporalit non rinunciato, ma diventa la questione del tempo e di essere. L '"temporalit" dello stanziamento che temporalizes la vicinanza a quattro dimensioni

4. Queste domande sono pervenute con Heidegger scritta nell'estate del 1970, dopo essere stato formulato dai redattori. Sono qui tradotto con il suo permis-

 

Sion.

 

 INTRODUZIONE

 

Introduzione "La messa a terra esplicito della differenza ontologica" si verifica nel "passo indietro" dal proseguire in ci che impensabile per l'identit, ma l'identit pensiero lo stanziamento. L a differenza ontologica scompare nella misura in cui il pensiero non pi persiste nel suo elemento impensato, la differenza ontologica non scompare in quanto il pensiero torna alla sua origine essenziali (identit e differenza, p. 65). 3. Essere. DOMANDA: Contrariamente alla Essere degli esseri, dovrebbe di per s Essere essere pensato come l'appropriazione? Qual il rapporto tra (a) pensare l'essere senza riguardo per gli esseri (che non significa metafisicamente come la pi alta e la terra degli esseri, causa sui), e (b) "Che cosa ne pensa della differenza se l'essere cos come esseri appaiono da O virt della differenza, ognuno a modo suo? " f (Identit e Differenza, pp. 63-64)? RISPOSTA: "Essere se stesso" si intende: L 'Stanziamenti non pu pi essere pensato come "Essere" in termini di presenza.' "Appropriazione" I nomi non sono pi un altro modo e per epoca di "essere". "Essere" pensiero senza riguardo per gli esseri (cio, sempre solo in termini di, e per quanto riguarda, li) significa allo stesso tempo: non pi concepito come "Essere" (presenza). Se questo accade, allora il pensiero pensa cos trasformato la seguente: la differenza ontologica scompare nello stanziamento attraverso il passo indietro. Si perde la sua determinazione per pensare e quindi abbandonato in un certo modo di pensare. Un'ultima domanda che avrebbe dovuto avere "rispose se stesso": Pu qualcosa di pi da dire sul rapporto tra (a) il epocale

7. Il cammino verso il linguaggio, trad. di Peter D. Hertz (New York: Harper & Row, 1971). p. 129n.

 

portando-presente vicino. L 'appropriazione senza destino (geschicklos) perch si invia presenza. Si tratta, tuttavia, non senza tempo, nel senso di vicinanza. Non n "in tempo" non nemmeno la "temporalit" di essere umano, ma piuttosto mette ciascuno in modo diverso in proprio. In "Essere e tempo", tuttavia, il rapporto tra lo stanziamento e l'essere umano dei mortali consapevolmente escluso.

2. Differenza ontologica. Domanda: La differenza ontologica scomparire nello stanziamento? Qual la differenza ontologica relative alle distinzioni (a) Essere e gli esseri, (b) essentia e existentia? Qual il significato della differenza ontologica nel seguente passaggio: '"la perenne verit dell'essere, fondata su esplicita la messa a terra della differenza ontologica, cio la distinzione tra gli esseri e l'essere (al di fuori di ogni metafisica ed esistenziale filoso-

 

PHY). "RISPOSTA: Identit e Differenza, una frase recita:" per noi, formulata in modo preliminare, la questione del pensiero la differenza quanto a differen e. ~ "~ tale, la differenza " identit ", pensava in termini dello stanziamento, il che significa il rapporto che perdura perdurance. Nella distinzione "Essere e gli esseri," la differenza sempre gi rappresentato senza pensiero, impensato per quanto riguarda la differenziazione. In tutte le epoche della metafisica, la differenza resta l'inspiegabile presupposto. L a differenza rimane senza posto e determinazione. Qui la distinzione di essentia-existentia appartiene sul lato di essere nel differenza impensato.

6. Cf. Identit e Differenza, trad. Stambaugh da Joan (New York: Harper & Row, 1969), p. 47.

 

xii

 

 INTRODUZIONE

 

trasformazioni di Essere, (b) Stanziamenti, e (c) espropriazione (kryptesthai)? Le trasformazioni epocali di Essere appropriazione-espropriazione Framing testa Uanus)

ONE

 

- TJI ..

Whatness e Thatness nella Metafisica o Essential Inizio: f idea e energeia

 

Stanziamenti non gi di per s una doppia relazione: (1) un rapporto "separabili che attraverso Framing eventualmente superare il gradino indietro le trasformazioni epocali di Essere dovrebbe essere assorbita in Stanziamenti, e (2) di un" rapporto inscindibile: appropriazione e di espropriazione non pu mai essere separati l'uno dall'altro, ma piuttosto costituiscono una relazione che la cosa pi originale di tutti (ma non originale, nel senso di essere una causa)? Tra le trasformazioni epocali di Essere e appropriazione regna la relazione del dare (Esgibt), ma nemmeno questo si pu dire del rapporto appropriazione-espropriazione.

 

Si potrebbe prendere la segue come una relazione storica sulla storia del concetto di Essere. Quindi ci che essenziale sarebbe mancato. Ma forse ci che essenziale, a volte pu certo dire in altro modo. "Essere" significa che gli esseri sono, e non sono inesistenti. "Essere" i nomi di questo "che" come la fermezza della insurrezione contro il nulla. risolutezza rese dal Essere al primo arriva di esseri, e qui in modo adeguato, anche. In questi esseri Essere appare. Cos ha deciso esseri vengono attribuiti a s (in essere) che questa non deve essere pensato espressamente. Esseri fornire informazioni adeguate circa l'Essere. "Esseri" sono considerate ci che reale. "Esseri sono reali." Questa frase significa due cose. In primo luogo: h T e del benessere degli esseri sta nella realt. Allora: come ci che reale, gli esseri sono "reali", cio, quello che veramente sono. L 'attuale l'atto di completamento o il prodotto di un'attivit. Questo prodotto di per s a sua volta, attiva e capace di attivit. L 'attivit di ci che reale pu essere limitato alla capacit di produrre una resistenza che si pu opporre a un altro cosa reale in modi diversi. P er quanto esseri che agiscono come ci che reale,

 

Xiu

 

1

 

 T H E fine della filosofia

 

Io

 

La metafisica come storia dell'essere

 

Essere si manifesta come realt. L a vera natura dell'essere si annunciato come "attualit", per lungo tempo. "Attualit" spesso significa "esistenza", troppo. Cos Kant parla di "prove dell'esistenza di Dio". Questo dovrebbe dimostrare che Dio reale, cio "esiste". "La lotta per l'esistenza", la lotta di tutto ci che (la vita vegetale, animale, uomo) di diventare e rimanere effettivo. Metafisica conosce la questione se il mondo reale, cio quella "esistenti" ora, il migliore dei mondi possibili o meno. Essere come la realt di ci che reale pronuncia il suo nome pi comune metafisico della parola "esistenza" (existentia). Nel linguaggio della metafisica "realt,", "realt" e di "esistenza" dicono la stessa cosa. Ma cosa dicono questi nomi non affatto univoca. Questo non dovuto alla sciatteria di uso delle parole, ma deriva piuttosto da all'Essere stesso. E 'facile per noi e ci piace fare appello al fatto che tutti sanno sempre quello che "essere", "realt", "realt" e "esistenza" dicono. Ma in che modo l'essere stesso determina come attualit di agire e dal lavoro oscuro. Inoltre, "Essere" non sarebbe del tutto il nome di metafisica se il detto del benessere degli esseri erano soddisfatti equiparare essere ed esistere. La metafisica ha contraddistinto per secoli tra ci che gli esseri sono e che gli esseri sono, o non lo sono. L 'linguaggio della metafisica scolastica conosce questa distinzione come quella tra essenza ed esistenza. Essentia: la quidditas, quella che, per esempio, l'albero come albero, come qualcosa di crescita, di vita, come albero, senza alcun riguardo per la questione se, e che questo o quel albero "esiste". Qui di albero determinata come gnos nel duplice senso di origine e specie, cio come la gallina a Polla. E 'l'uno come dove e come ci che comune a molti (koinon). nomi Essentia ci che qualcosa di simile a un albero esistente pu essere, se esiste, quella che rende possibile in quanto tali una cosa: la possibilit. L'essere diviso in whatness e thatness. L a storia dell'essere come metafisica comincia con la distinzione e la sua preparazione. La metafisica comprende la distinzione nella struttura della verit su esseri in quanto tale nel suo complesso. hus T l'inizio della metafisica si rivela come un evento che consiste in una determinazione di

 

Essere, nel senso di l'aspetto della divisione in whatness e thatness. Un supporto per la determinazione di differenziazione existentia ora data da Essentia. L'attualit si distingue dalla possibilit. Si potrebbe tentare di afferrare la divisione dell'Essere nella whatness e thatness da indagare l'elemento comune che determina ci che diviso. Che cosa che rimane ancora come ", " a prescindere da cosa e il che? Ma se questa ricerca di ci che pi generale conduce a vuoto, whatness deve essere colto come una sorta di thatness o, al contrario, questi ultimi devono essere colto come una degenerazione della prima? Anche se ci fosse successo, la questione circa l'origine della distinzione rimarrebbero. Proviene Essere se stessa? Che cosa "" Essere? Come funziona la venuta della distinzione, la sua origine, il risultato di Essere? r O semplicemente questa distinzione attribuita al Essere? Se s, con quale pensiero e con quale diritto? C ome viene data a tale attribuzione per l'attribuzione del genere? I f le questioni sollevate sono pensata anche approssimativamente, l'illusione di un corso o la materia, in cui l'Essentia o distinzione e segg existentia l'acronimo di ogni metafisica, scompare. L 'distinzione priva di fondamento se la metafisica tenta semplicemente di nuovo e di nuovo per definire i limiti di ci che diviso, e viene su con numerazione i costumi di possibilit e il tipo di realt che galleggiano nel vago via, insieme con la differenza di cui sono gi inserito. Tuttavia, se vero che i conti metafisica per la sua essenza attraverso questa differenza, in origine oscura, della quale e quello, e allora la sua essenza motivi, pu di per s mai venuto a conoscenza di questa distinzione. Essa dovrebbe essere in precedenza e come tali dalla avvicinato Essere che ha inserito questa distinzione. Ma essendo rifiuta questo approccio e, quindi, da solo rende possibile l'inizio essenziale della metafisica-alla maniera di preparazione e lo sviluppo di questa distinzione. L 'origine della distinzione di essentia ed existentia, per di pi l'origine delle Essendo cos divisi, resta nascosto, espressi alla maniera greca: dimenticato. Oblio dell'essere: l'auto-occultamento dell'origine della

 

 La fine della filosofia

 

La metafisica come storia dell'essere

 

Essendo diviso in whatness e thatness in favore di Essere che si apre esseri come esseri e rimane incontestata come Essere. Il divtsion in whatness e thatness non contengono solo un pensiero o dottrina metafisica. Si punta a un evento nella storia o Essere. Questo f f quello che deve essere pensato. Non sufficiente che tale raccoglimento per tracciare la distinzione comune tra essentia ed existentia alla sua origine nel pensiero dei Greci. E non affatto sufficiente "per spiegare", cio, per spiegare il terreno in termini di conseguenze, la distinzione che diventato decisivo per il pensiero greco, con l'aiuto della successiva formulazione concettuale comune per la metafisica degli scolastici. Si tratta, ovviamente, ~ t facile stabilire storicamente la connessione della distinzione tra essentia e existentza con il pensiero di Aristotele, che per primo ha portato la distinzione di un concetto, che , allo stesso tempo alla sua terra essenziali. Ci avvenuto dopo che il pensiero di Platone avevano risposto alla richiesta di essere in un modo che ha preparato questa distinzione, portando la sua istituzione allo scoperto. Essentia risponde alla domanda ti estin: che cosa (un essere)? Existentia dice di essere estin hoti: che . T h e la distinzione tra a estin nomi diversi. Essere (einai), si annuncia in una differenza. Come pu essere venuto a parte in questa distinzione? Quale essenza dell'essere si rivela in questa distinzione, come in l'apertura di tale essenza? All'inizio della sua storia, l'essere stesso si apre come emergenti (pbysis) e disvelatezza (aletbeia). Da qui si raggiunge la formulazione di presenza e permanenza nel senso di perenne (ousia). La metafisica vera e propria inizia con questo. Ci che appare in presenza-presente? Che cosa diventa mostra presentarsi al pensiero di Aristotele, come quella che si trova in una permanenza dover arrivare a uno stand, o si trova attualmente essendo stato portato al suo posto. L 'permanente parto attuale che si fatto avanti per disvelatezza in ogni caso questo e quello, a ti tode. Aristotele capisce ci che permanente, che giace in qualche modo presente come qualcosa a riposo. Resto risulta essere una qualit di presenza. Ma il resto un modo eminente di essere spostato. Motion si integra in riposo.

 

Che cosa spostato portato a stare in piedi e la posizione di una presentazione (verbale), ha portato in un far-via. Ci si pu verificare nel modo di physis (che consente di emergere qualcosa di se stesso) o nel modo di poiesis (per produrre e rappresentare qualcosa). L a presenza di presentare, se si tratta di qualcosa a riposo o in movimento, riceve la sua determinazione essenziale quando il movimento e, con essa, il resto come caratteristiche fondamentali dell'essere provenienti da presentare sono intesi come una delle modalit. Nella sua "Fisica", Aristotele distingue essere nel movimento e di essere a riposo come caratteristiche di presenza e interpreta queste caratteristiche in termini di essenza primordiale decisivo di essere, nel senso di rendere presente emergente in quello che palese. La casa in piedi esposto in disvelatezza, in quanto

 

casa, li risolto nel senso di completato boundary-Peras, telos-non nel senso di cessazione semplice. Resto conserva il completamento di ci che viene spostato. T h e casa vi come ergon. "Opera", ci che completamente a riposo nel resto esteriore appearancestanding, disteso in essa, che cosa completamente a riposo nel presentare in disvelatezza. H ~ ~ ~ nel modo tGreek, il lavoro non un lavoro nel senso di gh la realizzazione di un processo faticoso. Inoltre non risultato ed effetto. Si tratta di un lavoro nel senso di ci che si trova nella disvelatezza del suo aspetto esteriore e dura quindi in piedi o sdraiata. T o sopportare qui significa: essere presenti a riposo come lavoro. Ergon ormai caratterizza il modo di presentare. Presenza, ousia, significa quindi energeia: la presenza-as-lavoro (inteso presenza verbalmente) nel lavoro di lavoro-ness. Workness non significa attualit come il risultato di un'azione, ma piuttosto la presentazione, in piedi in disvelatezza, di ci che istituito. T h energeia u s,

 

 T H E fine della filosofia

 

La metafisica come storia dell'essere

 

pensato alla maniera greca, ha niente a che fare con la cosiddetta energia di epoche successive. Nel migliore dei casi vero il contrario, ma solo in un senso molto remoto. Invece di energeia, Aristotele utilizza anche il termine entelechia che lui stesso coniata. Telos il termine in cui il movimento della produzione e creazione di per s raccoglie. Questo incontro ritrae la-presente di ci che completata e si conclusa, cio, di ci che soddisfatto (il lavoro). Entelecheia sta avendo-(se stesso)-in-Alterminedi, il contenimento di rendere presente che lascia tutta la produzione alle spalle ed quindi immediato, puro: essere in presenza. Energeia, entelecheia sui mezzi lo stesso che a eidei en einai. Quali presenze in virt di "essere-in-the-lavoro-come-lavoro" il suo presente nella sua apparenza esteriore e attraverso il suo aspetto esteriore. Energeia l'ousia (presenza) del tode ti, del presente e del che in ogni caso. Poich questa presenza, ousia si chiama: a eschaton, la presenza nel-presente, che contiene tutto il possibile e definitiva. Questo modo pi alto di presenza concede anche il primo e pi vicina presenza di tutto ci che in ogni caso permane come questo e come quello in disvelatezza. Se 9being einai), ha cos determinato il pi alto del suo modo di rendere presente energeia, poi ousia cos fissata anche della sua propria esposizione di come si pu separare nella differenziazione dei whatness e thatness, e va quindi distinto anche in conseguenza della prevalente eminente di Essere come energeia. L 'distinzione di un duplice ousia (presenza) diventato necessario. L 'inizio del quinto capitolo del trattato aristotelico sulla "categorie" esprime questa distinzione. Ousia de estin lui kuriotata te kai kas protos legomene malista, ha Mete Tinos kath'hypokeimenou legetai Mete en estin hypokeimeno Tini, Anthropos tis hoion ho e ho tis ippopotami. "Quello che presente nel senso di rendere presente prevalentemente (presenza), che quindi basata in primo luogo e per la maggior parte quello che si predica n rispetto a qualcosa di gi davanti a noi, n (prima) si verifica in qualcosa di gi prima di noi, per esempio , l'uomo l, il cavallo l. "'

1. Cf. Ross traduzione: "Nel merito, nel vero e primo e pi preciso

 

Io

 

Quali presenze in modo non un predicato possibile, rendere presente nulla in o con un altro. Presenza in senso eminente e primario il persistere di qualche cosa che permane di se stesso, si trova presente, il persistere della persona in ogni caso, l'ousia del kath'hekaston: L 'questo, T lui singolare. In termini di presenza cos definita, la presenza di altri si distingue il cui rendere presente cos caratterizzato: deuterai de ousiai legontai, en hois eidesin hai protos ousiai hyparchousin legomenai, Tauta te kai ton ta gene Eidon Touton: Anthropos tis hoion ho it uomini eidei hyparchei a antropologici, genos tou de eidous stima di zoon. deuterai oun hautai legontai ousiai, te hoion ho anthropos kai di zoon. (Categ. V, 2 bis, 11 e segg.) "Ci che presente nel secondo grado, tuttavia, sono quelli (notare il plurale), in cui ci che si parla come presenza di primo grado (in quanto tale in ogni caso) domina gi come nel modo di aspetto esteriore. L '(dal nome) maniere di aspetto esteriore e anche le origini di queste modalit appartengo a questo posto, per esempio, questo uomo sta l in l'aspetto esteriore di un uomo, ma per questo aspetto esteriore' uomo, 'l' origine (del suo aspetto esteriore) 'l'essere vivente.' Cos ci che presente nel secondo grado sono questi: ad esempio, 'uomo' (in generale) e anche 'l'essere vivente' (in generale). "2 Presenza in senso secondario la stessa mostra di aspetto esteriore a cui tutti origini fanno parte anche, in cui ci che persiste in realt permette che come presenze che per emergere. Presenza nel senso primario l'Essere che si esprime nella estin hoti: che qualcosa , existentia. Presenza nel secondario

senso della parola, quello che non n prevedibile n di un soggetto presente in un soggetto, per esempio, il singolo uomo o di cavallo. "-All note in questo libro sono stati forniti dal traduttore. apprezzamento espresso a Frank per Oveis la sua assistenza nella traduzione di brani latino. 2. Ibid.: "Ma in un certo senso secondario queste cose si chiamano le sostanze all'interno del quale, come specie, le sostanze primarie sono inclusi; anche quelli che, come generi, anche la specie. Per esempio, l'uomo singolo incluso l'uomo la specie ', e per il genere a cui appartiene la specie ' animale ': questi, dunque, vale a dire, l'uomo la specie' e il genere 'animal1-sono denominati sostanze secondarie ".

 

 -

 

T H E fine della filosofia

 

Io

sense is Being, to which we trace back in the ti estin: what something is, essentia. That something is and what something is are revealed as modes of presencing whose fundamental characteristic is energeia. But doesn't a quite different, more far-reaching distinction underlie the difference of hoti estin and ti estin, namely that of what presences and presencing? In this case, the difference as such first named lies on one side of the distinction of beings and Being. T h e hoti estin and the ti estin name manners of presencing to the extent that what is present in them presences in the lasting of each thing or else remains hidden in the mere showing itself of outward appearance. T h e distinction between what something is and that it is comes from Being (presence) itself. For presencing has within itself the difference of the pure nearness of lasting and of levels of being in the origins of outward appearance. But how does presencing have this diference within itself7 As familiarly as the distinction of essentia and existentia together with the difference of Being and beings offers itself for thinking, the essential origin of these differences is just as obscure, and the structure of their belonging together just as indefinite. Perhaps metaphysical thinking in accordance with its essence can produce no understanding for the enigmatic character of these differences which are a matter of course for it. Nevertheless, since Aristotle thinks ousia (presence) in the primary sense as energeia and since this presence means nothing other than what in a changed interpretation is later called actualitas, "actuality" and "existence" and "reality," the Aristotelian treatment of the distinction reveals a priority of the later so-called existentia over the essentia. What Plato thought as the true, and for him sole, beingness (ousia) of beings, presence in the manner of idea (eidos), now moves to the secondary rank within Being. For Plato, the essence of Being gathers itself in the koinon of the idea, and thus in the hen which, however, is determined as the unifying One by physis and logos, that is, by the gathering allowing-to-emerge. For Aristotle,

8

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

1

Io

 

,

1

 

;

 

Being consists in the energeia of the tode ti. In terms of energeia, eidos can be thought as a manner of presencing. In contrast, the tode ti, the actual being, is incomprehensible in its beingness when thought i n terms of idea. (The tode ti is a me on-and yet an on.) Still, the historical relationship of Aristotle to Plato is established even today by explanations, variously nuanced, as follows: In contradistinction to Plato, who held that the "Ideas" were "what is truly existent," allowed for individual beings only as seeming beings (eidolon), and demoted them to that which really ought not to be called beings (me on), Aristotle took the free-floating "Ideas" back from their "supraheavenly place" and planted them in actual things. In doing this, Aristotle thought the "Ideas" as "forms" and these "forms" as "energies" and "forces" housed in beings. This curious explanation, inevitable in the progression of metaphysics, of the relationship between Plato and Aristotle with regard to the thinking of the Being of beings calls forth two questions: How should Aristotle be able at all to bring the Ideas down to actual beings if he has not in advance conceived the individual actual being as that which truly presences? But how should he reach the concept of the individual real being's presence, if he doesn't previously think the Being of beings in the sense of the primordially decided essence of Being in terms of presencing in unconcealment? Aristotle does not transplant the Ideas (as if they were things) into individual things. Rather, he thinks for the first time the individual as the actual, and thinks its lasting as the distinctive manner of presencing, of the presenting of eidos itself in the most extreme present of the indivisible, that is, no longer derived, appearance (atomon eidos). T h e same essence of Being, presencing, which Plato thinks for the koinon in the idea, is conceived by Aristotle for the tode ti as energeia. In that Plato can never admit the individual being as what is truly in being, and in that Aristotle, however, conceives the individual together with presencing, Aristotle is more truly Greek in his thinking than Plato, that is, more in keeping with the primor9

 

~

 

1

 

;

 

,

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

1

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

dially decided essence of Being. Still, Aristotle was able to think ousia as energeia only in opposition to ousia as idea, so that he also keeps eidos as subordinate presence in the essential constitution of the presencing of what is present. However, to say that Aristotle is more truly Greek in his thinking than Plato in the way described does not mean that he again comes closer to the primordial thinking of Being. Between energeia and the primordial essence of Being (aletheia-physis) stands the idea. Both modes of ousia, idea and energeia, form in the interplay of their distinction the fundamental structure of all metaphysics, of all truth of beings as such. Being announces its essence in these two modes: Being is presence as the showing itself o outward appearance. Being is f the lasting o the actual being in such outward appearance. This double f presence in-sists upon presence, and thus becomes present as constancy: enduring, lasting. T h e two modes can be thought only by saying each time, from the vantage point of beings relative back to beings, what they are and that they are. Within its history as "metaphysics," Being limits its truth (unconcealing) to what is in being in the sense of idea and energeia. Energeia takes precedence without, however, ever being able to repress idea as a fundamental characteristic of Being. T h e pro-gression-to be taken here in its literal meaning-of metaphysics from its beginning, which Plato and Aristotle ground, consists in the fact that these first metaphysical determinations of presence change and also draw the mode of their mutual distinction into this change. Finally, their distinction disappears in a peculiar confounding.

 

T h e pro-gression of metaphysics from its essential beginning leaves this beginning behind, and yet takes a fundamental constituent of Platonic-Aristotelian thinking along. This tradition, of which

 

itself retains knowledge and later on specifically reports upon in a historical manner, gives rise to the illusion that the transformation which pro-gressed from the essential beginning of is the preservation of the genuine fundamental constituents and at the same time its progressive development. This illusion has its real support in the opinion, which has long since become public property, that the fundamental concepts of metaphysics remain everywhere the same. Idea becomes idea, and this becomes representational thought. Energeia becomes actualitas, and this becomes actuality. Even though the linguistic formulations of the essential constituents of Being change, the constituents, so it is said, remain the same. If changing fundamental positions of metaphysical thinking develop on this foundation, then their manifoldness only confirms the unchanging unity of the underlying determinations of Being. However, this unchangingness is only an illusion under whose protection metaphysics occurs as history of Being. In this history, the two differentiated modes of Being, whatness as idea and thatness as energeia, each assumes a different criterion for the manner in which Being holds itself in the determination of what is in being. When it becomes valid as Being, whatness encourages the predominance of looking at what beings are, and thus makes possible a peculiar precedence of beings. Thatness, in which nothing seems to be said about beings themselves (about their "what"), is enough to establish that beings are, whereby the "is" and Being thought in that "is" are simply taken for granted. When it becomes valid as Being, thatness makes it possible that the essence of Being is assumed as self-evident. Both factors, the precedence o beings and the f assumed self-evidenceof Being, characterize metaphysics. Because thatness remains unquestioned everywhere in its nature, not, however, with regard to actual beings (whether they are o r are not), the unified essence of Being, Being as the unity of whatness and thatness, also determines itself tacitly from what is unquestioned. Thus the history of Being is primarily revealed in the history

 

 T H E E N D OF PHILOSOPHY

 

of energeia which is later called actualitas and existentia, actuality and existence. But is actuality only the translation for the same essence of energeia retained in its sameness? And does existentia preserve that fundamental characteristic of Being which in general received its form in ousia (presence)? Ex-sistere speculo means for Cicero to step out of the cave. One might suspect here a deeper relation of existentia as stepping out and forward to coming forward to presence and unconcealment. Then the Latin word existentia would preserve an essential Greek content. That is not the case. Similarly, actualitas no longer preserves the essence of energeia. T h e literal translation is misleading. In truth it brings precisely another transposition or misplacement to the word of Being. This transposition of another type of humanity to the whole of beings occurs by virtue of the closure of Being. T h e character of that-being and of the "that" has changed. In the beginning of metaphysics, beings as ergon are what presence in their being produced. Now ergon becomes the opus of the operari, the factum of the facere, the actus of the agere. T h e ergon is no longer what is freed in the openness of presencing, but rather what is effected in working, what is accomplished in action. T h e essence of the "work" is no longer "workness" in the sense of distinctive presencing in the open, but rather the "reality" of a real thing which rules in working and is fitted into the procedure of working. Having progressed from the beginning essence of energeia, Being has become actualitas. Thus in the horizon of historical description, a transition from the Greek to the Roman conceptual language has come about. But in order to realize sufficiently even merely historically the scope of this transition, the Roman character must be understood in the full wealth of its historical developments, so that it includes the politically imperial element of Rome, the Christian element of the Roman church, and the Romantic element as well. With a peculiar fusion of imperial and papal elements, the Romantic becomes the origin of that fundamental structure of the modernly experienced

 

Io

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

reality called cultura ("culture"), and for various reasons was unknown to the Greeks and the Romans, and to the German medieval period as well. When counted in epochs, the determination of Being as actualitas thus extends throughout the whole of Western history from the Romans u p until the most recent of modern times. Because the essential determination of Being as actualitas underlies all history in advance, that is, at the same time the structure of relationships of a certain type of humanity to beings as a whole, all Western history since is in a manifold sense Roman, and never Greek. Every subsequent reawakening of Greek antiquity is a Roman renovation of that Greece already reinterpreted in a Roman way. T h e Germanic character of the medieval period, too, is Roman in its metaphysical essence, because it is Christian. Ever since the transformation of energeia to actualitas (reality), the real is truly what is in being and thus decisive for everything possible and necessary. But Being as actualitas is in itself historical, in that it accomplishes the truth of its essence and in that it thus makes possible the fundamental positions of metaphysics. T h e distinction at the beginning maintains itself in Being throughout: Actualitas is differentiated as existentia from potentia (possibilitas) as essentia. Actualitas preserves nothing of the essence of energeia over and above the indefinite relation to the work. And yet the essence of Being at its beginning still prevails in actualitas, too, since whatness is determined as idea. T h e fundamental characteristic of idea (cf. "Plato's Doctrine of Truth," 1942) is the agathon. Outward appearance showing itself makes beings capable of becoming present as this and that. Idea as whatness has the character of aitia, cause. Origination from its whatness dominates in every coming-to-be of beings. Whatness is the matter of every thing, that is, its cause. Accordingly, Being is in itself causal. As a consequence of the Platonic determination of Being as idea, that is, as agathon, the decisive role of aitia unfolds in the essence of Being. Here the character of being-responsible-for as

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

making possible does not necessarily and exclusively have the character of effective working. Still, the precedence of aitia gets so firmly fixed in the beginning of metaphysics that it takes over the place of the prernetaphysical determination of Being as arche; more exactly: it brings about the transformation of the character of arche to that of aition. Soon the equation of arche and aitia, in part already with Aristotle, becomes a matter of course. Being shows the essential characteristic of the making possible of presence, that is, of effecting constancy o r permanence. Thus, in spite of the gap between energeia and actualitas, the transformation to Being as esse actu is prepared from the metaphysical essence of Being at its beginning, too. When Being has changed to actualitas (reality), beings are what is real. They are determined by working, in the sense of causal making. T h e reality of human action and divine creation can be explained in terms of this. Being which has changed to actualitas gives to beings as a whole that fundamental characteristic which the representational thinking of the biblical-Christian faith in creation can take over in order to secure metaphysical justification for itself. Conversely, through the dominance of the Christian-ecclesiastical interpretation of beings, the fundamental position of Being as reality attains an assumed self-evidence which has remained decisive ever since for all subsequent understanding of the beingness of beings, even apart from the attitude of strict faith and its scholarly interpretation of beings as a whole. T h e predominance of the determination of Being as reality, now immediately comprehensible to everyone, gets firmly fixed so that soon, conversely, energeia is understood in terms of actualitas, and the primordial Greek essential character of Being is once and for all misunderstood and made inaccessible by the Roman interpretation of Being. T h e tradition of the truth about beings which goes under the title of "metaphysics" develops into a pile of distortions, no longer recognizing itself, covering up the primordial essence of Being. Herein lies the reason for the necessity of the "destruction" of this distortion. when a

 

Io

,

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

,

 

Io

 

,1

 

thinking of the truth of being has become necessary (cf. Being and T i m e ) But this destruction, like "phenomenology" and all hermeneuticaI-transcendental questions, has not yet been thought in terms of the history of Being. Real beings are what truly is, because actuality constitutes the true essence of thatness; for actuality thought as energeia is the fulfilled presence of the actual being. But the more the presencing being endures in a lasting manner, the more actual it remains. Esse, in contradistinction to essentia, is esse actu. Actualitas, however, is causalitas. T h e causal character of Being as reality shows itself in all purity in that being which fulfills the essence of Being in the highest sense, since it is that being which can never not be. Thought "theologically," this being is called "God." It doesn't know the state of possibility because in that state it would not yet be something. In every not-yet there lies a lack of Being, in that Being is distinguished by permanence. T h e highest being is pure actuality always fulfilled, actuspurus. Effecting is here the persisting presencing of itself of what persists for itself. This being (ens) is not only what it is (sua essentia), but in what it is, it is always also the persistence of what it is (est suum esse non participans alio). For this reason, metaphysically thought, God is called the summum ens. T h e apex of his Being, however, consists in his being the summum bonum. For the bonum is causa, and as $nis the causa causarum. Thus, precisely with respect to causalitas (that is, actualitas) the bonum is what gives persistence to everything that persists and is thus prius quam ens; causalitas causae Fnalis est prima. There is not a moral characterization or even an idea of "value" contained in the statement "Deus est summum bonum. " T h e name summum bonum is rather the purest expression for the causality which is appropriate to the purely real, in accordance with its effectuating the persistence of everything that can persist (cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theol. I, qu. 1-23). Ontologically understood, the bonum thought with regard to the summum ens is the echo of the Platonic agathon, that is, what absolutely makes capable,

 

 T H E E N D OF PHILOSOPHY

 

1

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

Aristotle thought it originates in that change of the essence of truth from the unconcealment of beings to the correctness of the reasoned This change already begins with Plato and underlies the beginning of metaphysics. Although this origin, which is likewise already metaphysical, echoes indefinitely enough in the concept ex-sistentia, too, ex-sistentia receives its decisive meaning from actualita~, that is, with regard to causalitas. In his Disputationes metaphysicae (XXXI, sect. IV n. 6), whose influence continuing into the beginning of modern metaphysics has meanwhile become more evident, Suarez says this about ex-sistentia: nam esse existentiae nihil aliud est quam illud esse, quo formaliter, et immediate entitas aliqua constituitur extra causas suas, et desinit esse nihil, ac incipit esse aliquid: sed huiusmodi est hoc esse quo formaliter et immediate constituitur res in actualitate essentiae: ergo est verum esse existentiae. ' Existence is that Being through which a being is truly and immediately established outside of the causes with the result that nonbeing ceases, and an actual being begins to be. Ex-sistentia is related in each case to one being in accordance with the underlying distinction in Being. What a being is in each case is established by existence in the sphere outside of causality. This means: Whatness undergoes a causal realization in such a way that what is thus produced is released as a product from causality, and established on its own basis as something real. T h e "extra" is no longer related like the Aristotelian exo to the dianoia, to human reason, but rather to a transpiring causality. Ex-sistentia is actualitas in the sense of the res extra causes et nihilum sistentia, a production which transposes something into the realm outside of causality and actuality, the realm of being produced, and thus overcomes nothingness (that is, the lack of real beings). But if ex-sistentia is placed in the realm outside of causality, how

3 . "For the being of existence is nothing but that being by which some entity is formally and immediately established outside of its causes, and ceases to be nothing, and begins to be something: And indeed of such a kind is this being by which a thing is formally and immediately established in the actuality of essence: Therefore it is the true being of existence."

 

namely for beings as such-what makes possible: the condition of possibility (cf. "Plato's Doctrine of Truth"). But also in the actualitas, which is determined in every respect by causalitas, the essence of beingness at the beginning maintains itself in a changed form: presence. The summum ens is distinctively characterized by omnipraesentia. However, "ubiquity," (to be present everywhere) is also determined "causally." Deus est ubique per essentiam inquantum adest omnibus ut causa essendi (qu. 8a, 3). T h e interpretation of existentia can also be explained by the causal character of reality. This is the name for the other concept which is mostly equated in meaning with actualitas (reality), and is even used far more often in the conceptual language of metaphysics, above all in the distinction of essentia and existentia ("essence" and "existence"). T h e origin of the word existentia is traced back to two passages in Aristotle's Metaphysics which both treat almost identically the on hos alethes, the Being of beings in the sense of "unconcealed" (Met. E 4, 1027b 17 and Met. K 8, 106Sa 2lff.). Here Aristotle speaks about a exo ousa tis physis tou ontos and about the exo on kai choriston. T h e exo, outside, means the Outside tes dianoias, that is, human reason which permeates beings in discussion, and in doing so establishes what it has talked about. What is established in this way consists and presences only for such discussion and in the neighborhood of its activity. What is outside (exo) consists and stands as something persisting in itself in its own place (choriston). What thus "stands outside," ex-sistens, the ex-isting, is nothing other than what presences of itself in its being produced, the on energeia. At this point, a derivation of the Latin word ex-sistentia from an Aristotelian explanation of beings is called for. More important for insight into the history of Being is the fact that the characterization of what presences of itself (ousia) is already based upon a changed essence of truth. T h e "true" is still called alethes, the unconcealed; but what is true, namely the proposition, is true not because it itself as revealing is something "unconcealed," but rather because it establishes and thinks what is unconcealed by the adequation of reason. T h e determination of Being in the sense of ex-sistentia as

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY Metaphysics as History of Being

 

can actualitas still determine the essence of existence? not exi5 tence the taking leave of causality? On the contrary. In that exis tence exposes from the area of causality to the openness of which is now a real being based upon itself and thus an effectiv being, existence is precisely dependent upon causality. Placing an, establishing, the making-stand of ex-sistentia, is what it is out causality, but only out of it. T h e ex-sistentia is the actus, quo rt sistitur, ponitur extra statum possibilitatis. It alone can and shotlld ex-pose from the cause the thing as caused, that is, produced. T h e usual name for thatness, existence, testifies to the pre,cedence of Being as actualitas in this interpretation. The dominance of its essence as reality determines the progression of the history Being, throughout which the essential determination once begun i: carried out to its prefigured completion. T h e real is the existing. The existing includes everything which through some manner of causality constituitur extra causas. But because the whole of beings is the effected and effecting product of a first producer, an appropriate structure enters the whole of beings which determines itself as the co-responding of the actual produced being to the producer as the highest being. T h e reality of the grain of sand, of plants, animals, men, numbers, CO-respondsto the making of the first maker. It is at the same time like and unlike his reality. The thing which can be experienced and grasped with the senses is existent, but so is the object of mathematics which is nonsensuous and calculable. "M exists" means: this quantity can be unequivocally constructed from an established point of departure of calculation with established methods of calculation. What is thus constructed is thus Proven as something effective within a context of calculative proof. "M" is something with which one can calculate, and under certain conditions must calculate. Mathematical construction is a kind of constitution of the constituere extra causas, of causal Being is given in the essence of reality, and reality determines the existence of what exists. Being presences as effecting in the unified-manifold sense according to which what effects, but also

 

what is effected and also what is the effected-effectingand the effective being, is what-is. T h e being thus determined in a manifold way in virtue of effecting is real. ~t can only be recollected that Being has been given to the essence of reality. Recollection points back to the previous essence of ~~i~~ in the sense of worklike and visible presenting. T h e progression out of this essence allows the agathon and the airion to become determining. The essential origin of Being as making possible and as causing rules t h r o u g ~ o thefuture history of Being. Makingpossible, caunng, accounting u~ for are determined in advance as gathering in virtue of the One as what 25 unifying This unifying is neither an intertwining nor an assembling. T h e hen in which the essence of Being rests has the Character of concealing-unconcealing, of the gathering to be thought, The unity of the One is shown throughout the hi nor^ of ~ ~in various forms whose differences stem from the change of i ~ g essence of aletheia, of concealing-unconcealing. ~f as a consequence of this event beings have meanwhile 10% since and generally been experienced and have been the subject opinion, this opining can still never encroach upon the strange uniqueness of even this essence of Being. T h e opining about Being as reality does veil the event of this essential origin. But opining can never harm the decisiveness in virtue of which this essence of Being brings the progression of its history to its utmost completion.

 

'

 

1

 

~

8

 

THE TRANSFORMATION

 

OF T R U T H T O CERTAINTY

 

The hidden history of Being as reality also first makes possible various fundamental positions within beings. These western fundamental positions ground in each case the truth about Being on the basis of what is real and establish and make this truth certain for what is real. Even though the essence of Being as reality fixates as ultimate an irrevocable change in the face of worklike Presence (energeia), still the question of how effecting and reality are deter-

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

accordance with the precedence of beings which starts with the beginning of metaphysics, Being, meanwhile represented as the general determination (koinon, k~tholou, genur, commune) of beings, takes its essential shape in virtue of an authoritative being. What real being the authoritative effecting effects as the determination of reality's essence cannot be calculated and can only be established historically. Since the creator god as first cause is what primarily effects, and since his effects, however, are the world, and within the world the true effector is man; the triad: God, world (nature), man circumscribes the realm of possibilitirc according to which one of these realms of what is real takes over th structuring of reality's essence. Assuming, however, that the detel mination of reality in accordance with what is authoritatively re: also does not primordially come from beings, but rather stems fror Being itself; then the development of reality's essence within metaphysics must also point to this origin. An indication of thi becomes apparent in the fact that the actual essence of truth, il whose light a period of mankind experiences beings, participates il the history of Being. T h e manner of this participation remains, 0 course, profoundly veiled. Truth, meanwhile in metaphysics changed to the distinctivl trait of the intellect (humanus, divinus), comes to its ultimate essence which is called certainty. The name expresses the fact that truth concerns consciousness as a knowledge, a representation which is grounded in consci0uSneS~ such a way that only that knowledge in is valid as knowledge which at the same time knows itself and what it knows as such, and is certain of itself in this knowledge. Certainty here is not to be taken only as an addition to knowledge in the sense that it accomplishes the appropriation and the possession of knowledge. Rather, certainty is the authoritative mode of knowledge, that is, ''truth," as the consciousness, conscious of itself, of what i! known. T h e mere having of something in consciousness is, in con. either no longer knowledge or not yet knowledge.

20

 

,

'

 

~h~~ truth becomes certainty in essence is an event whose beginning is inaccessible to all metaphysics. On the other hand, in connection with this essential change of truth, a peculiar preeminence of humanity within what is real soon becomes evident. and at the same time, however, also a corresponding role of what is unconditionall~real, thought in a theological manner. As knowing beings, both realities, God and man, are metaphysically the bearers the reality of knowledge and certainty. of truth and thus However, it lies in the essence of certainty to be certain of itself case, that is, to claim for itself the final assurance of itself. in certainty thus first and alone determines the reality of what is real1 which at first appears to be only its actual support. By thus exhibiting its support in terms of the essential claim to the self-accomplishmerit of its self-assuring, it kindles the battle between the possible supports of its essence. Before all, the creator god, and with him the institution of the offering and management of his gifts of grace (the church), is in sole possession of the sole and eternal truth. As actus purus, ~~d is pure actuality and thus the causality of everything real, that is, the source and the place of salvation which as blessedness guarantees eternal permanence. By himself, man can l ~ become, and be, absolutely certain of this salvation. O n the other hand, through faith and similarly through lack of faith1 man is essentially established in the attainment of salvation's certainty, Or forced to the renunciation of this salvation and its certainty- Thus a necessity rules, hidden in its origin, that man make sure of his salvation in some fashion in the Christian or in another sense (salvation: soteria: redemption: release). The origin, belonging to the history of Being, of the dominance of truth as certainty is concealed in the release of its essence from the primal truth of Being. Assurance of himself and of his effectiveness determines the reality of man. T h e possibility is contained here of man's determining the essence of certainty by himself in accordance with the essence of certainty in general (self-assurance), and thus

 

~

 

e

 

~

 

1

 

21

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

upon and builds u p of himself what is real as what has an effect upon him and as what he effects. What is real becomes what can be effected within that human activity which, knowingly basing itself upon itself, cultivates everything and takes care of it. Thus "culture" begins historically as the structure of humanity which is certain of itself and intent upon the assurance of itself (cf. Descartes, Discours de la mtthode). Culture as such is elevated to the "goal," or, what is essentially the same, it can be set u p as the means and value of humanity's dominance over the earth. T h e Christiz church attains a position of protective defense. T h e decisive actic of this defense consists in taking over the stance of this new adve sary, who at first still moves and establishes himself within t1 Christian world. T h e Christian church becomes Christianity culture. Conversely, however, culture, that is, the self-certainty humanity which has become assured of its effectiveness, strives fit Christianity into its world and to incorporate the truth of Chri tianity into the certainty of humanity certain of itself and of i possibilities for knowledge. In that truth becomes the certainty of knowledge of humanil making sure of itself, that history begins which is called the mode period in the historical calculation of epochs. T h e name says moi than it means. It says something essential about this age. In that tf truth in which its humanity stands demands the development of the assurance of absolute dominance, this essence of truth delivers man and his effecting over to the inevitable and never ceasing worry of increasing the possibilities of safety and making sure of them again in the face of newly enkindled dangers. Man and his effecting advance in the continually new elements of his successes and discoveries, in the continually newest elements of his attainments and conquests, in the continually unheard of elements of his experiences. This attainment of safety and this arrangement of what is real in safety is able to dominate the historical movement of moder humanity only because the relation of man to everything re: changes in the premonitory beginning of this history, in that tl1

 

,

 

1~

 

,

 

Io

 

truth of beings has become certainty, and certainty since then is developing its own essential fullness as the authoritative essence of But this change of the essence of truth from the cor,ctness of the thinking proposition to the certainty of representational thinking, too, is determined as reality by the essence of Bring. Thus the change of essence of truth gives an indication for the way in which Being itself begins to complete its essence as reality. What is truly real (actuspurus) is God. Reality (actualitas) is the effecting causality which of itself brings about the stabilizing of independent constancy. Causality, however, is not exhausted in the effectuation of the constancy on earth of all that is not divine, that is, created. T h e highest causality is the actuspurus as summum bonum, which as the final goal (finis) predestining everything and thus .levaring everything to its true constancy anchors all reality of what is real in the first cause. For this reason, that real being which is man, created in the image of God, must above all bring about his reality by holding fast to the highest good, that is, by faith (fides, qua creditur). Through faith, man is certain of the reality of the highest real being, and thus at the same time also of his own real continuance in eternal bliss. T h e causality of the highest real being allots to man thus created a definite kind of reality whose fundamental characteristic is faith. In faith rules certainty, that kind of certainty which is safe even in the uncertainty of itself, that is, of what it believes in. What is believed in is that real being whose reality as actus purus binds and directs all human activity in its plans and ideas. Man can stand in such a commitment only if he of himself and as himself bows down toward something committing him, frees himself for what he believes in such bowing down, and is free in such a way. Man's freedom ruling in faith and its certainty (propensio in bonum cf. Descartes, Meditationes de prima philosophia IV, "De vero et falso") develops as the essential structure of created man only when all human behavior, in its own way, bears within itself that fundamen-

 

 v

THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

tal character in relation to everything real, in its own way, whi Presents and assures what is real to effecting man each case. Man, however, does not just relate through faith to God and the world created by God. Man also relates to what is real throu the lumen mturale. In the natural light of reason, a certainty nativ to him must become authoritative if certainty decides about th adequate relation to what is real. All natural human behavior an

as

 

something true is that which man of himself clearly and dis-

 

ior must be certainty. This demand for the self-protection of his natural constant accomplished by man himself does not come from a revolt again! the doctrine of faith. O n the contrary, it is the necessary conscquence of the fact that the highest truth has the character of the Certainty of salvation. T h e essential transformation of truth to the certainty of representational thinking is determined by the essence Of Being as actuspurus. For this reason, the world of Christian faith remains authoritative throughout manifold transformations for the organization and cultivation of what is real (for culture) in the of the modern period, but it is also authoritative for the interpretation of what is real in terms of its reality (for modern metaphysics). Modern culture is Christian even when it loses its faith. O n the other hand, Christianity tries in all ways to remain capable of being cultural and to be a Christianity of culture, most of all where the Christianity of faith is furthest removed from original Christianity. If the natural ideas, brought about by man himself, about what is real are thus supported and guided by truth as certainty, every real being placed in a truth, every true being (ens verum) must be

 

thus represented has also already presented what is constant, that s, what is real, to representational thinking. Reality is representation in the sense of the constancy of the iontinuou~which is set up by certain representational thinking and

is

 

for it.

of

 

rt is true that in the beginning of the essential transformation

 

,

 

of reality whose history fulfills modern metaphysics as Being, this essence is not yet expressed as such. O n the contrary. It almost seems as if in the beginning of n~odernmetaphysics the traditional essence of reality, actualitas, is maintained just as it is, and only the manner of comprehension of what is real, knowledge, is subjected to a special inquiry ("theory"). T h e essence of Being in the beginning of modern metaphysics is actually ambiguous in that a manifold of essential possibilities of the essential completion reality appears which later coalesces, developed from original unity. The ambiguity of the essence of reality in the beginning of n d e r n metaphysics is the sign of a genuine tt-ansition. In contrast, the supposed singleness of meaning which is presumably expressed in the cogito ergo sum is an illusion.

4. "And accordingly it seems to me that already I can establish as a generai that all things which I perceive very clearly and very distinctly are t n ~ "

 

24

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Certainty as the essence of truth claims of itself to have a manner, thoroughly adequate for itself, of knowability and of what can be added and built up as truly real through certainty in knowledge, and thus assured in constancy. Certainty is the assurance of everything represented which grounds itself in its own essence and is entrusted to that essence alone. For this reason, certainty requires an underlying support sufficient for it which expressly lies continually present for representing as the ground for all representational construction and bringing about of what is real. If the essence of truth, having become certainty, brings about ' its adequate relation to what is real through and for man who is placed in the essence of truth by requiring him to construct what is knowable as that which can be produced with certainty; and if the certainty for this construction requires that basis in which certainty's own essence is incorporated as the foundation, then something real must be secured in advance for all representational thinking whose reality, that is, persistence, is removed from every threat to representational thinking in the sense of dubitability. T h e demand for certainty goes after a fundamentum absolutum et inconcussum, a basis which no longer depends upon a relation to something else, but rather is absolved from the very beginning from this relation, and rests within itself. Which real being is appropriate to be such a basis, in such a way that it can at the same time change to suit the essence of reality (the , constancy for all representational thinking) prepared by certainty?

 

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

has come to be along with what is already present the symbebekota. this name, the character of presencing and thus the Greek essence of Being (ousia) can still be heard. However, because the symbebekota only presence along with, only come as an addition to what endures of itself, and only have stability along with it, they are in a certain way a me on, something present which does not attain the pure manner of lasting of the actual, the hypokeimenon. In accordance with the change of energeia to actualitas, the change of hypokeimenon to subiectum obscures the essence of Being thought in the Greek manner, in spite of the correct translation. The subiectum is what is placed and thrown under in the actus and can then be joined by other things. In this joining, in the accidens, presencing-al~ng-within presence, that is, a manner of presencing, can no longer be heard. What underlies and has been placed under (subiectum) takes over the role of the ground upon which other things are placed so that what has been placed under can also be conceived as what stands under, and thus is constant before everything. Subiectum and substans mean the same thing: what is truly constant and real, what suffices for reality and constancy and is therefore called substantia. Soon the essence of hypokeimenon determined at the beginning, of what lies present of itself, is interpreted from the perspective of substantia. Ousia, presence, is thought as substantia. T h e concept of substance is un-Greek, but it dominates together with actualitas the essential character of Being in the metaphysics to follow. However, just as the Aristotelian characterization of "existens" is determined as exo tes dianoias on through the change of truth from aletheia to homoiosis and through the concomitant transposition of truth to the proposition (logos), the same essential change of truth and the predominance originating from it of the kataphasis (logos) takes over the preparation of a far-reaching ambiguity and reinterpretation of the hypok'eimenon. Since it is what of itself lies present, what truly is becomes kath'hou legetai ti, that of which something shown and stated (legomenon) is predicated and attributed as what is

 

U p to and still during the beginning of the modern period, what is real is the ens actu, what effects and is effected in its relative constancy. In contrast, in the beginning of metaphysics, Being presences not as actualitas (actuality), but as workness (energeia) for which the lasting of the actual suffices. T h e actual lies present of itself, it is the true hypokeimenon. Aristotle calls everything which

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

underlying. T h e hypokeimenon is now in turn the legomenon (logos) kath'hauto, that which is addressed directly and only as itself, thus becoming accessible as a being. T h e logos, the proposition, now characterizes what underlies as such and signifies what presences of itself, and thus remains the substratum of all predication and negation. Ever since, all essential determinations of beings as such, that is, characterizations of what-is, remain within the confines of the kataphasis, that is, of the kategoria. They are categories. Because logos shapes the essence of what underlies, it becomes the determination ' of that which arche and aitia are, of what is later called the underlying ground and cause. T h e "subiectum" subsequently becomes the name which names the subject in the subject-object relationship, and also the subject in the subject-predicate relationship. ! T h e change of metaphysics at its beginning releases energeia into actualitas, ousia into the substantia, aletheia into the adaequatio. Similarly, logos, and with it hypokeimenon, comes into the sphere of meaning of the translation ratio (rheo, rhesis = speech, ratio; reor = to predicate, to opine, to justify). Ratio is accordingly the other name for subiectum, for what underlies. Thus a characterization for human (predicating) behavior comes to play the role of the concept for that which constitutes a being in its true Being, in that as what lasts it is constant in itself, and thus is what stands under all beings, ' however they may be, the substantia. T h e ground, understood as the essence of the beingness of beings, receives the not-at-all obvious name of ratio in subsequent metaphysics. Everything that endures of itself and thus lies present is hypokeimenon. Subiectum is a star and a plant, an animal, a human being and a god. When a fundamentum absolutum et inconcussum is required in the beginning of modern metaphysics which as a true being suffices for the essence of truth in the sense of certitudo cognitionis humanae, a subiectum is being asked for which already lies present in all representing and for all representing, and is what is constant and standing in the sphere of indubitable representational thinking.

 

Io

 

Representational thin king (percipere, co-agitare, cogitare, repraesentan in uno) is a fundamental characteristic of all human behavior, even of n o n e p i s t e m ~ l ~ g ibehavior. From this perspective, all behav~al ioral actions are cogitationes. However, what constantly already lies present for representational thinking during representation which presents something to itself is the representer itself (ego cogitans), before which everything represented is brought, to which and back to which (re-praesentare) it becomes present. As long as representing continues, the representing ego cogito is also expressly what already lies present in representing and for it. Thus the distinctive character of continually already lying present, of the subiectum, belongs to the ego cogito cogitatum in the sphere of the essential structure of representational thinking (perceptio). This constancy is the permanence of that which can never be doubted in any representing, even if this representing is itself a kind of doubting. The ego, the res cogitans, is the distinctive subiectum whose esse, that is, presencing, suffices for the essence of truth in the sense of certainty. This esse circumscribes a new essence of the existentia which Descartes defines as a veritas aetema (axiom) in section 49 of his Principiaphilosophiae as follows: is qui cogitat, non potest non existere, dum cogitat. "Whoever behaves toward something while representing cannot not continually effect while r e p r e ~ e n t i n g . ~ Reality is characterized as constancy by permanence (the persistence of representational thinking). But at the same time it makes the representing being into an ens actu. T h e effecting of the new essence of reality of this distinctive real being has the fundamental characteristic of representational thinking. Accordingly, the reality of what is represented and added in all representing is characterized by being represented. Thus begins the development of a characteristic of the essence of reality which is later on first conceived by Kant in all clarity as the objectivity of the object. Representational thinking brings about

5 . "He who thinks must exist while he thinks."

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

the presentation of the opposition of the object. As long as we think metaphysically and not, in a manner inappropriate to Being, psychologically, reality as being represented never signifies that what is real is a mental-spiritual product and effect of representational activity, and thus something which only exists as a mental structure. O n the contrary, as soon as the fundamental characteristic of representing and being represented comes to power in the essence of reality, the constancy and persistence of what is real is narrowed down to the sphere of presencing in the presence of the re-praesentatio. T h e character of presence prevailing in the metaphysical essence of Being which was not fully obliterated, only changed, even in the transformation of energeia to actualitas (cf. the omnipraesentia of the actuspurus), now appears as presence within representational thin king (repraesentatio). Descartes' Meditations, which treat the distinction of the subiectum man as the res cogitans, think Being as the esse of the ens verum qua certum. T h e newly thought essence of the reality of what is real is not yet called by a name of its own. This by no means signifies that the Meditations turn away from the Being of beings to the knowledge of beings. For the Meditations are characterized as Meditationesdeprimaphilosophia,thus as meditations which keep within the sphere of the question about the ens qua ens. These Meditations are a beginning, indeed a decisive beginning, of the true start of the metaphysics upon which the modern period rests. But how little the whole conversion to the metaphysics of the modern period is already accomplished here can be seen from the fact that the res cogitans, as fundamentum absolutum et inconcussum the eminent subiectum, is at the same time a substantia Fnita, that is, creata, in the sense of traditional metaphysics. T h e reality of the substantia jinita is determined by the causality of the causa prima. The distinction of the mens humana among other subiecta is expressed by the fact that it notior est quam corpus. This precedence in being known is not a matter of easier comprehensibility, but rather signifies the truer presence of the res cogitans in the sphere of human representing as a presenting to onesev Human representing itself

 

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

Io

 

Io

 

Io

 

1

Io

 

and the representing human being are here more constant, more and more in being than all other beings when thought from the new essence of reality. In accordance with this distinction of its lying present as subiectum, the men1 humana thus claims in the future the name "subject" exclusively for itself, so that subiectum and ego, ,,biectivity and I-ness become equivalent. T h e "subject" as the name for that about which something is predicated loses its metaphysical dignity in appearance only. This dignity appears in Leib.iz and is developed fully in Hegel's Science of Logic. At first, however, all nonhuman beings still remain ambiguous with respect to the essence of their reality. They can be determined by being represented and by objectivity for the representing subiecturn, but also by the actualitas of the ens creatum and its substantiality. On the other hand, the sole supremacy of Being as actualitas in the sense of the actuspurus is broken down. Within its metaphysical truth as the beingness of beings, the history of Being begins to bring the various possibilities of its essence to unity, and thus the fulfillment of its essence to completion. It is evident in the earliest beginning of this history that it claims the essence of man with a peculiar decisiveness. T h e full beginning of the history of Being in the form of modern metaphysics occurs where the essential completion of Being determined as reality is not yet accomplished as such, but where the possibility of the decisiveness of this completion is totally prepared for, and the ground of the history of completion thus laid. T o take upon himself this preparation of the completion of modern metaphysics, and thus everywhere to rule this history of completion, is the determination of the history of Being of that thinking accomplished by Leibniz. Since the beginning tradition of metaphysics following Aristotle, every true being is a hypokeimenon. This hypokeimenon is determined afterwards as subiectum. Descartes' thinking distinguishes the subiectum which man is to the effect that the actualitas of this subiecturn has its essence in the actus of cogitare (percipere). But what if the actualitas should contain this basic trait of the

 

 7

T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

percipere in general? HOWcould it happen that this essential characteristic of the actualitas remained concealed? T h e prevailing essence of truth in each case decides about the manner and the scope of revealedness of the essence of Being. When truth has become certaint^, then everything which is truly real must present itself as real to the real being that it is. All effecting is now revealed as a selfeffecting in effecting. T h e essence of this effecting is not fulfilled in the mere effecting of something. All effecting is rather in itself, and not just incidentally, a self-effecting. In effecting lies the essential characteristic which is perhaps most readily named by the expresion ''coming toward itself," because this expression doesn't anticipate. Effecting is in itself related to itself, and it is only in this relation that it determines its effecting. However, that in relation to which the "coming toward itself" presences does not need to be an I or a self. T h e "coming toward itself" can be conceived as turning-back (repexio) with regard to the progression of effecting to what is effected. Nevertheless, the question must remain open to where this turning brings back, and what it really represents. Every effecting is an effectuation which brings itself about. By bringing something before itself each time, it accomplishes a presentation and thus represents what is effected in a certain way. Effecting is in itself a representing (percipere). T o think the essence of reality more appropriately, more in its own being, now means in the realm of the essence of truth as certainty: to think the essence of the perceptio (representation) with regard to the question of how the essence of effecting and reality develops itself more fully from that essence.

 

,

,

 

,

,

 

LEIBNIZ: BELONGING-TOGETHER THE OF REALITY AND REPRESENTATION

In what way representation, thought sufficiently in an original and complete way, constitutes the fundamental characteristic of the reality of what is real, and thus in what way every being is only

 

truly in being as a representing being, can be seen in the fact that the beingness of beings (the substantiality of substance) and representation are the same, thought from a fundamental determination This fundamental determination of beings as such is the ambiguity returns, which runs through all meta,,ity. physics, according to which "unity" means the actual "one" determined by unity, but also this determining unity itself. Similarly, ousiameans a beingness (a being), and Being as the essence of beings. When Leibniz thinks the "monad," he thinks unity as the essenT h e essential fullness which gives the tial constitution of its precision stems, however. from the beequivocal title thinking. In a letter longingtogetherofreality and of April 30, 1687, to Arnauld (Gerhardt, ed.. Die philosophischen ~ ~ b ~ Gi w k i~ n i~ , 11, 97), Leibniz says: ' B u r trancher court, / b z je tiens pour un ariome cette proposition identique qui n'est diversifice que par 1 'accent, savoir que ce qui n kt pas viritablement un Ptre, 'est pas non plus viritablement un &re." U n Ptre, what presences from the actual unifying one; un etre, a presencing (presence) which as such conrains unity. In the letter of June 20, 1703, to de Voider (Gerh. 1 7 1 251), we find the sentence: "Quodsi nullum vere UnUm adest, omnis Vera res erit sublata. "7 What truly unifies produces the presence of every thing. Unity constitutes the beingness of beings. But this applies only to true unity. 1t consists in an original, that is, simple, unification resting within itself. This unification gathers and enfolds in such a way that what is enfolded is represented and presented to what unifies, and thus at the same time unfolded. Unity in the sense of this simple enfolding and unfolding unification now has the character of representation. ~ 1 representation presents a manifold to the self-con1

short, I consider as an axiom this identical proposition, which receives two 6, meanings on\y through a change in accent; namely, that what is not truly being is not truly a being." 7. u ~ u if there were no true one, then every true being would be eliminated." t

@

 

'

 

Io

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

tained unifying being, and constitutes the state of the one (that is, of the real being). T h e manifold thus presented is limited in each case in that, granting God as the infinite being, the whole of beings can never be presented in a created being. Every state of the monad produced by representation is thus in itself in transition to the next state, and thus essentially transitional. Accordingly, section 14 of the Monadology reads (Gerh. VI, 608 ff.): "L Vtat passager qui enveloppe et reprisente une multitude dans l'uniti ou duns la substance simple n 'est autre chose que ce qu 'on appelle la Perception, qu'on doit bien distinguer de 1 'apperception ou de la conscience. . . T h e essence of representation is determined here not psychologically, but solely with regard to the essence of the beingness of beings, as their fundamental trait. T h e metaphysical essence of representation is stated in an abridged and thus easily misunderstood version in a sentence in a letter of July 11, 1706, to des Bosses (Gerh. 11, 3 1 1 ) : "Cum perceptio nihil aliud sit, quam multorum in uno expressio, necesse est omnes Entelechias seu Monades perceptione praeditas esse, neque ulla naturae Machina sua Entelechia propria caret. '? T h e perceptio is an essential expression of the monad. It helps to constitute the monad's unity as the beingness of beings. It has its own essence in "expressing a manifold in unity." T h e expressio is a presenting unfolding, a de'velopper (Gerh. IV, 523), which belongs to the gathering enfolding, envelopper, and is understood expressly as reprisenter. T h e "perceptions" are "les reprisentations du composi, ou de ce qui est dehors, dans le simple" (Principes de la Nature et de la Grace,fondis en raison, Gerh. VI, 598).1 T h e unum in which the multa are unfolded, that is, explicated and presented in a collected manner, is the "simple." T h e simple, unifying of itself,

8. "The passing condition which involves and represents a multiplicity in the unity, or in the simple substance, is nothing else than what is called Perception. This should be carefully distinguished from Apperception or Consciousness . . ." 9. "Since perception is nothing else than the expression of many in one, it is necessary that all entelechies, or monads, be provided with perception. N o natural machine lacks its own entelechy." 10. "Representations of the compound, or of what is external, in the simple."

 

Io

,

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

presents the manifold to itself, and has the essence of its self-containedness, its constancy, that is, its reality in this presenting representation itself. Leibniz does not understand the Aristotelian word entelecheia in Greek manner, but rather in the sense of his monadologic thinking: "On pourrait donner le nom d7Ente16chies d touter les substances ou Monades crib, car elles ont en elles une certaine per-ction jechousi to enteles), il y a une suflsance (autarkeia) qui les rend sources de leurs actions internes et pour ainsi dire des Automates incorporels. " I 1 (Monadologie paragraph 18, cf. paragraph 48.) In accordance with its "n~rsistent"activity of unifying, the monad has a certain completer--- - ness working within itself which constitutes its actualitas (reality). "True unity," that is, the substantiality of substance, is contained in t h e essence of this reality as simple, unifying, representing effec. . - -. tuation. ". . . Dico substantiam . . . esse una Entelechia actuatam, sine qua nullum esset in ea principium verae Unitatis. "'2 I n contrast, the unity of those entia, which are such entia per aggregationem, is a unity "a cogitatione; idemque est in quovis aggregato, ut nihil vere unum invenias, si Entelechiam demas. "I3 (Letter of June 20, 1703, to de Volder, Gerh. 11, 250.) However, what the unifying representation unfolds and presents to representation is no arbitrary multum, but rather a definitely limited manifold in which the universe is mirrored. T h e manifold is in each case the world, mundus, but representing itself according to the modus spectandi, in which the perceptio of the monad is held. In accordance with this manner of seeing and its point of

- -

 

11. "The name of entelechies might be given to all simple substances or created monads, for they have within themselves a certain perfection (echousi to enteles); there is a certain sufficiency (autarkeia) which makes them the sources of their internal activities, and so to speak, incorporeal automata." 12. "1 say that a substance is actuated by one entelechus without which it would contain no principle of true unity." 13. "Whose unity comes from thought. This is the same in every aggregate; you will find no true unity if you take away the entelechy."

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

view, the world is concentrated in such a way that the universe mirrors itself in effecting unifying representation, and every monad itself can be addressed as a living mirror of the universe, effecting of itself. In the fifth letter to Clarke, Leibniz says with great conciseness: "chaque substance simple en vertu de sa nature est, pour dire ainsi, une concentration et un miroir vivant de tout l'univers suivant son point de vue. "" (Gerh. VII, 41 1, n. 87.) Because every being is determined as monad in its reality by simple unifying effectuation in the sense of representation from its point of view, the monads ("entelechies") are necessarily of themselves different from each other: "Entelechias differre necesse est, seu non esse penitus similes inter se, imo principia esse diversitatis, nam aliae aliter exprimunt universum ad suum quaeque spectandi modum, idque ipsarum oficium est ut sint totidem specula vitalia rerum seu totidem Mundi concentrati. "I5 (Letter of June 20, 1703, to de Volder, Gerh. 11, 2 5 1 / 5 2 . ) T h e unfolding-gathering essence of the perceptio is thus first revealed in the simple originality of "world formation" and in mirroring effecting itself. But this, too, only hints at the essential realm of the perceptio, although in such a way that its fundamental characteristic as effecting (actio) first becomes evident, and the essential core of the actualitas is determined. Representation-presenting the universe from a point of view and representing it only in a concentration corresponding to the point of view and thus never attaining what is truly sought after-is in itself transitional in that it is essentially together with its actual world and drives beyond that world through its relation to the universe. A progression driving beyond itself is thus active in representation: principium mutationis "est inter14. "Every simple substance is by its nature (if one may say so) a concentration and a living mirror of the whole universe, according to its point of view." 15. "Entelechies must necessarily differ or not be completely similar to each other; in fact, they are principles of diversity, for they each express the universe from their own point of view. This is their office, that they should be so many living mirrors or so many concentrated worlds."

 

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being omnibus substantiis simplicibus, . . . consistitque in progressu perceptionurn Monadis cuiusque, nec quicquam ultra habet tota rerum natura. "I6 (Letter of June 30, 1704, to de Volder, Gerh. 11, 271.) In accordance with its own essence, representation is transitional in that it drives toward transition. This striving is the fundamental characteristic of effecting in the sense of representing. "L 'actio, du principe interne, qui fait le changement ou le passage d'une perceptiond une autre, peut 2tre appeli Appktition; il est vrai, que 1 'apphit ne saurait toujours parvenir enti2rement d toute la perception ou il tend, mais il en obtient toujours quelque chose, et parvient h des perceptions nouvelle~. (Monadologie, section 1 5 , Gerh. VI, 609.) T h e striving "I7 (appetitus) in which the monad effects its own unity for itself is, on the other hand, essential representing in itself. T h e simple selfcontainedness of what is truly persistent (persistens, to de Volder, January 21, 1704, Gerh. 11, 262) consists in representing as striving. Perceptio and appetitus are not two determinations of the reality of what is real which are first produced. Rather their essential unity constitutes the simplicity of what is truly one, and thus its unity and its beingness. "lmo rem accurate considerando dicendum est nihil in rebus esse nisi substantias simplices et in his perceptionem atque appetitum" (Letter of June 30, 1704, to de Volder, Gerh. 11, 270).18 T h e simple unifying unity is originally effecting in accordance with the manner of representational striving. This originally effecting unity is the point of departure for everything transitional and transitory in beings, from which stems the relation to the one totality of the All. This relation rules in all occurrences in advance. This

16. "The principle of change is internal to all simple substances, . . . and it consists in the progress of the perceptions of each monad, the entire nature of things containing nothing besides." 17. "The action of the internal principle, which causes the change of the passage from one perception to another, may be called appetition; it is true that desire cannot always completely attain to the whole perception to which it tends, but it always attains something of it and reaches new perceptions." 18. "Indeed, considering the matter carefully, it may be said that there is nothing in the world except simple substances and, in them, perception and appetite."

 

Io

1

'

1

 

Io

 

1

 

,

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

unity is principium internum. Leibniz calls the principle of beings as such: vis, L force, force. T h e essence of force is not determined by a the retroactive generalization of something effecting which we experience somewhere, but the other way around: the essence of force is the original essence of the beingness of beings. What truly is shows itself in the light of the truth which has become certainty, as the cogitare of the ego cogito. T h e essence of force is defined in reflection upon the Being of what truly is. It is only from this essence of force that individual forces receive the character of their dependent (derivative) essence. T h e first version of section 12 of the Monadology says this clearly: "Et ghiralement on peut dire que la force n'est autre chose que le principe du changement. " I 9 "Change" does not mean here any kind of becoming-different in general, but rather the transitional essence of striving representation in accordance with whose manner every being is, insofar as it is. Force, the fundamental characteristic of simple unifying unity, is thus also adequately called vis primitiva activa because it rules pure effecting in its essence in a simple and original way. It is the subiectum and the basis (Monadologie, section 48), the underlying supporting constant in whose effecting the constancy of beings have their closest origination, although not a radically producing origination (originatio radicalis). Every subiectum is determined in its esfe by vis (perceptio-appetitus). Every substantia is monad. Thus the essence of the reality of the res cogitans developing in the light of truth as certainty attains its scope in which it rules everything real. Together with the universality of the representational essence of reality, the fundamental characteristic of representing, striving, reveals itself so that unity as the essence of beingness first gains its full character from the essence of vis. Thus the new essence of reality begins to permeate everywhere and explicitly the totality of beings. In such a manner,

19. "And one can say generally that force is n o t h ~ n g other than the principle of change."

 

Io

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

the beginning of that metaphysics develops which will remain the ground of history of the modern period. At the same time, however, what is effecting in such a way (monadi~ally) retains that characteristic of reality which distinguishes the actualitas as causalitas T h e causa prima is the suprema substantia. But its effecting also changes in accordance with the essential change of reality. As essential production in the sense of striving, the effecting of the original unity, "Unit6 primitive, " (Monadologie section 47) emanates to the individual real being which has its limitation in the manner of its point of view. In accordance with that range of view (perspective), the capability is determined of mirroring the universe in such and such a manner, that is, of allowing it to shine. For this reason, the created substances, too, originate so to speak "par des Fulgurations continuelles de la DivrnitC de moment d moment" (Monadologie, section 47).20In this continual fulguration from moment to moment of the divinity of the god, sparks originate striving toward light, and correspondingly let the light of the divinity continue to shine, and copy it. Everything real is monadical in its reality: not, however, in the same way, but in gradations. Thus Leibniz can say: "Meae enuntiationes universales esse solent, et servare analogiam. 'I2' (Letter of July 11, 1706, to des Bosses, Gerh. 11, 3 11.) Leibniz's thinking stands under the necessity of the essence of Being thus revealed, which produces what is real in its actual reality in the simplicity of representing and striving unification and thus suffices for the essence of the constancy of what is self-contained. "Facile enim vides simplices substantias nihil aliud esse posse quam fontes seu principia [simul et subjects] totidem perceptionis serierum sese ordine evolventium . . . quibus suam perfectionem quantum fas fuit suprema substantia in substantias multas ab ipsa pendentes difudit, quas singulas tanquam concentrationes universi et (alias prae aliis) tanquam divinitatis

20. "by continual fulgurations of the Divinity from moment to moment." 21. "My propositions are usually universal and retain analogy."

 

II

 

'

 

1 I

 

Io

Io

 

Io

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

imitamenta concipere oportet. "(Undated letter to de Volder, Gerh. 11, 278.)22 Striving and representational effecting is the essence of the esse of every subiectum This essence constitutes the fundamental character of existentia. In accordance with the essence of truth which, having become certainty, requires Being as representing self-production, a being, if it is going to exist at all, must exist in this way insofar as it exists. "Neque alias rerum rationes puto intelligi et (summatim) vel optari posse, et vel nullo vel hoc mod0 res existere debuisse." (1.c.y3 But since the beginning of metaphysics, the existentia which then first came to essence has had precedence over the essentia in that the essential character of reality determines that of possibility. This does not exclude the fact that, in reverse, what is possible previously determines what is correspondingly real. In the beginning of metaphysics, the prote and the deutera ousia still develop from the essence of presence which is not explicitly grounded. Soon they let this origin become completely forgotten, particularly in the transition from energeia to actualitas. Thus potentia and actus appear as two manners of Being which is not determined more precisely. T h e necessitas joins these two in subsequent metaphysics as the third modality. T h e new essential appearance of reality in the beginning of modern metaphysics brings along the related change of the potentia, so that the distinction of essentia and existentia changes as a distinction, too, until it is completely reabsorbed in the presencing of

22. "You can easily see that simple substances can be nothing else than just as

 

Io

 

Metaphysics as History o Being f

 

11

1

,

 

many sources or principles [and also subjects] of perception of series disclosing themselves in order. . . by which the supreme substance scattered its perfection, as much as possible, into many substances depending upon itself, which substances are to be conceived of individually as concentrations of the universe and as imitations (some more than others) of divinity." 23. "1 think that no other reasons for things could be understood or (in brief) desired: A thing ought to exist in this or no other way."

 

Being itself with the renewed essential character of reality as something essentially unconditional. It is only from the change of the nature of the existentia already accomplished that Leibniz's short treatise "De primae philosophiae Emendatione, et de Notione Substantiae" (1694; Gerh. IV, 468 ff.) eceives its true import right down to the title. Looking back to the traditional distinction of potentia and actus, the vis is characterized, SO to speak, as the intermediate being between the two. In truth, this overcoming the previous concepts of possibility and reality. T h e inquiry, however, is in the service of the improvement of "first philosophy" which asks about the beingness of beings and acknowledges the substantia as what truly is. Vis is the name for the Being of self-contained beings. Accordingly, this Being consists neither in the actualitas, in that it means the production of what merely lies present, nor in the potentia in the sense of the predisposition of a thing for something (for example, of the tree trunk for a wooden beam). T h e vis has the character of conatus, of the already driving endeavor of a possibility. T h e conatw is in itself nisus, the inclination to realization. Tendentia thus belongs to vis, and signifies the striving to which representational thinking belongs. Endeavoring, inclined self-exerting production is the fundamental trait of the constancy in virtue of which actual beings bring themselves about, that is, develop to a mundus concentratus. Representing, striving stabilization is the nature of existentia. T h e modalities "possibility" and "necessity" are modi existendi. T h e nature of the existentia which is expressed for the first time shows its authoritative emanation throughout all the fundamental characteristics of beingness and its corresponding basic principle "of the ground" in twenty-four short sections which Leibniz once wrote down. T h e hidden succinctness and cogency of these sentences, seemingly just following each other, first gives us a glimpse of the simplicity of Being which here claims the thinking of a thinker. T h e "treatise" (Gerh. VII, 289-291), still undated, has no title. We shall call it "The Twenty-four Statements" (cf. pp. 49-54).

 

ll

 

Io

 

1

 

Io

 

1

 

1

 

 7

T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

Metaphysics as History of Bang

 

Io

 

1

 

they Cannot replace the ninety sections of the Monadology which are similarly constructed. But Leibniz's thinking really first attains the culmination of its mysterious transparency in these "twent~-fourstatements." Instead of a thorough interpretation of the "twenty-four statements" which would have to indicate the crux of the implied history of Being, it will be sufficient to mention what directly concerns the nature of the existentia. Being in the sense of the hoti estin says that something is, and that there is not rather nothing. Thatness (existentia) is revealed as the insurrection against nothingness (ex-sistereex njhjlo) in that nothingness means absolutely nonexistent. However, as soon as Being enters the essence of effecting, and beingness actually means reality, like a procedure and an effort, an action of the actul is in every being (res, thing, chose) as an effected being. Because nothing is needed for it and because every arrangement is superfluous, nothingness is simpler and easier than the real being thus effected. "Car le rien est plus srmple et plus facile que quelque chose. " 2 4 (Princi~es la Nature et de fa GrGce, fondts en raison, n. 7; Gerh. VI, de 602.) But in that beings are, and Nothingness has already made itself known anyhow as what is easier and simpler, the question must be asked: '%urquoi il y a p l ~ t 6 tquelque chose que rien?"2s (1.c.) This question about the "why" is, of course, only necessary and justified if everything, and thus also the precedence of what is less simple and easy (that is, beings), has its "therefore," that is, its ground before nothingness. T h e question is supported by the "grand principlen of "metaphysics" which says: "que rien ne se fait sans railon sufisante. "26 (1.c.) But if this ''principle" names the essential beginning of what somehow relinquishes nothingness, the principium grande must eminently ~haracterize insurrection against nothingness, and thus the

24. '" 26. "Nothing happens without a sufticlent reason

 

Of

 

like ground: hvpOkeimenon, subiectum. Being as reality is a grounding.

 

,

1

 

(The Twenty-four Statements," n. 6.)

 

tion of itself. Thus possibility does not repulse reality, but contains it, retains it in itself, and so remains precisely in possession of its essence whose fundamental trait is appetitus. Hence the first of "The Twenty-four Statementsv can begin with the sentence: "Ratio eft in Nutura, cur aliquid potius existat quam nihil." " A ground is in the nature of beings as beings, a reason why something, that is, preferentially and more attractedly, exists rather than nothing." T h i s says: beings in their Being are exigent with respect to themselves. "To existy1 means in itself: attraction and unifying capability which is an effecting. I n that something is it is a h 0 e ~ ~ e n t i a lpotius. ly

27 " ~ h every poss~blecan be said to strive to exist." u ~

 

1

 

1

 

Io

 

,

1 I

 

42

 

Io

 

--

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Being as existence in the sense of representational striving which simply and unifyingly effects a mundus concentratus (the monad) as speculum universi is the new nature of actualitas. T h e prevalence of existentia over nonexistentia belongs to it. But the essential structure of Being which thus comes to light would not be metaphysical, which it is, if the causalitas which has ruled Being since Plato's agathon were not still determinative in the nature of actualitas as vis primitiva activa. The metaphysical basic characteristic o f the monadic nature o Being appears in the progression o the $rst four f f statements: T h e ratio (cur aliquidpotius existat quam nihil) "debet esse in aliquo Ente Reali seu causaVz8 2). In contradistinction to the ens mentale (n. (ideale), the ens reale is for Leibniz in each case a res actu existens. T h e ens reale, which underlies all rationes as their causa, "hoc autem Ens oportet necessarium esse, alioqui causa rursus extra ipsum quaerenda esset cur ipsum existat potius quam non existat, contra Hypothesin. Est scilicet Ens illud ultima ratio Rerum, et uno vocabulo solet appellari DEUSWZ9 (n. 3). T h e god who acts here as ground is not thought theologically, but purely ontologically, namely as the highest being in whom all beings and Being itself are caused. However, because Leibniz thinks every manner of Being as modus existendi in virtue of the monadically determined existentia, the ens possibile is not only thought as existituriens, but the ens necessarium is also thought as existenti$cans. T h e fourth statement: "Est ergo causa cur Existentia praevaleat nonExistentiae, seu Ens necessarium est EXISTENTIFICANS." 'O With

28. "The ground (why something exists rather than nothing) 'ought to be in some real being or cause'. " 29. "But this being must be necessary; otherwise, a ground would again have to be sought why it exists rather than not--contrary to our hypothesis. That being is, of course, the ultimate ground of things and is usually designated by the one word GOD." 30. "Therefore there is a cause why existence prevails over nonexistence, that is, necessary being is that which causes to exist."

 

Io

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

1

Io

 

1

 

1

 

Io

 

this determination of the facere, Being's character of production appears in the sense that Being itself is made and effected by a being. But within the causal nature of beingness permeating metaphysics everywhere in the most various forms, the exigent nature of Being still becomes determinative in the developed beginning of modern metaphysics. T h e eminence of the exigere, however, does the representational character of Being; for this charnot acter preserves the tradition of the beginning and primal essence of Being which becomes evident as presencing. But now presence has come to be in the repraesentatio in virtue of ousia and presence through the veritas as certitudo. However, this presence would be thought too one-sidedly if it were equated with presence in the sense of the representation of what is represented for representing. T h e essence of repraesentatio, and thus of Being in the sense of vis and existentia, now enters a peculiar ambiguity. In that it appropriates a world as a perspective of the universe, every monad is originally mirroring from its point of view. In that the monad is representative in such a way, it portrays itself and represents itself, presents itself and thus represents what it requires in its striving. It is what it represents in this manner. T o represent something does not just say: to bring something to oneself, but also: to portray something, namely the representing meant in the first instance. A man "represents something" means: he is somebody. This Being belongs to vis. As vis and existentia, Being is at the same time this "representing something," which in turn is always variously brought in the individual monads by these monads themselves to themselves, but first of all and as a whole in the omnipraesentia of the highest substance as the central monad. What is everywhere essential is the fact that "presence" is explicitly related back to a kind of ego, and is really accomplished by that ego as its own essential activity. In contradistinction to this representative presence, the presence whose name is ousia is a presencing to and from unconcealment, whereby unconcealment is experienced, but no longer itself grounded in its essence.

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Correspondingly, noein is to be thought as representing only with caution, namely when it has its essential weight in dwelling in unconcealment and when this dwelling, attentive to unconcealment, perceives it. Bringing to itself what is encountered in the safety of what is presented is something quite different from dwelling in unconcealment. Noein and percipere name essentially different kinds of representation. For Being, which already predetermines what can be represented, is in the first instance hypokeimenon, and in the second instance objectivity which is grounded in a subiectum, but in a subiectum whose essence is not identical with that of hypokeimenon.

 

Io

'

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

In its developed beginning, modern metaphysics brings the essence of Being as reality in the manner of the history of Being to an essential plurality which from then on can never be enunciated in a unified way, and is thus always distorted in some respect by retroactive terms. But perhaps precisely for this reason the first attempt at a contemplation of the history of Being might make use of such terms, even if this procedure only serves the next task of for once preparing for the event that the recollection in this history, nearest to us in time, of the self-contained multiplicity of Being's essence must come to meet us. T h e term serving such an intention may be called subiectity. T h e common name subjectivity immediately and all too stubbornly burdens thinking with erroneous opinions which interpret every relation of Being to man, or even to his egoness, as a destruction of objective Being, as if objectivity in all its essential traits did not have to remain caught in subjectivity. The name subiectity should emphasize the fact that Being is determined in terms o the subiectum,but not necessarily by an ego. Moreover, the f term contains at the same time a reference to the hypokeimenon, and thus to the beginning of metaphysics. It also presages the progression of modern metaphysics which actually does claim egoness,

 

i

Io

 

i

 

above all the selfhood of the spirit, as an essential characteristic of true reality. If one understands by subjectivity the idea that the essence of reality is in truth-that is, for the self-certainty of self-consciousness ,men1 sive animus, ratio, reason, spirit, "subjectivity" appears as a manner of subiectity. Subiectity does not necessarily characterize Being in terms of the actualitas of representational striving, for subiectity also means that beings are subiectum in the sense of ens ,ctu, whether this is actuspurus or mundus as ens creatum. Subiectity says finally: beings are subiectum in the sense of the hypokeimenon which has the distinction of being prote ousia in the presencing of what is actual. In its history as metaphysics, Being is through and through subiectity. But where subiectity becomes subjectivity, the subiectum preeminent since Descartes, the ego, has a multiple precedence. T h e ego is on the one hand the truest being, the being most accessible in its certainty. But it is also and as a consequence that being in which we think Being and substance in general, the simple and the composite (Monadologie, section 30, Gerh. VI, 612), insofar as we think at all. Finally, spirit, mens, has a precedence within the gradation of monadic beings. "Et Mentium maxima habetur ratio, quia per ipsas quam maxima varietas in quam minimo spatio obtinetur. " ("The Twenty-four Statements," n. 21.) In the mentes, an eminent representing and striving is possible, and thus the effecting of an eminent presence. "Et dici potest Mentes esse primarias Mundi unitates" (n. 2 2). However, for the modern history of metaphysics, the name subjectivity expresses the full essence of Being only when Being's character of representation is not thought about simply or even predominantly, but rather when appetitus and its developments as a fundamental characteristic of Being have become evident. Ever since the developed beginning of modern metaphysics, Being is will, that is, exigentia essentiae. "Will" contains a manifoldness of essence. It is the will of reason o r the will of spirit, it is the will of love or the will to power. Because the will, and thus also the representation active in it,

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

are known as human faculties and activities, it seems as if a thorough humanization of Being had come about. As modern metaphysics and thus all metaphysics comes closer to its completion, anthropomorphism is expressly required and adopted as the truth, although the fundamental position of anthropomorphism is grounded by Schelling and Nietzsche in different ways. T h e name subiectity names the unified history of Being, beginning with the essential character of Being as idea u p to the completion of the modern essence of Being as the will to power. T h e multiplicity of the modern essence already takes shape in the developed beginning of modern metaphysics: Being is reality in the sense of indubitable representation. Being is reality in the sense of representational striving which in each case unifies a being which is a world in terms of simple unity. As such unification Being is actualitas. However, as effecting (being attracted) reality, Being has the fundamental characteristic of will. As this willing, Being is the stabilization of constancy which still remains a becoming. In that every willing is self-willing, Being is eminently characterized by "coming toward itself" whose real essence is attained in reason as selfhood. Being is the will to will. All of these characteristics of Being which belong to subiectity as subjectivity develop a unified essence which, in accordance with its exigent character, develops itself and thus the whole of beings in its own unity, that is, in the conformation of its essential structure. When Being has attained the essence of will, it is in itself systematic and a system. T h e system, thought as the unity of order of knowledge, appears at first to be merely the paradigm of portrayal for everything knowable in its structure. But because Being as reality is itself will, and will is the unification of the unity of totality striving for itself,

 

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

 

;

 

Io

Io

 

the system is no mere schematic order which the thinker has in ,ind and always presents only incompletely and each time somehow onesidedly. T h e system, the Sustasis, is the essential structure of the reality of what is real--of course, only when reality has been discovered in its essence as will. This happens when truth has become certainty, evoking from the essence of Being the fundamental &aracteristic of the universal ensurance of structure in a ground which ensures itself. Because veritas does not yet ground its essence in the certitudo of the cogitare in the medieval period, Being can never be systematic. What is called a medieval system is always just a summa as the presentation of the whole of doctrine. But the idea of a system is still less commensurate with the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle. T h e systematic essence of subjectivity first brings the trend toward the unconditionality of manipulation and positing. Here the essence of condition appears as a new form of the causality of beingness, so that reality is true reality only when it has determined in advance of everything real all that is in terms of the systematics of the conditioning unconditioned. LEIBNIZ," T h e TWENTY-FOUR STATEMENTS"~'

1. Ratio est in Natura, cur aliquid potius existat quarn nihil. Id consequens

 

Io

 

~

 

Io

Io

 

est magni illius principii, quod nihil fiat sine ratione, quemadmodum etiam cur hoc potius existat quam aliud rationem esse oportet.

2. Ea ratio debet esse in aliquo Ente Reali seu causa. Nihil aliud enim causa

 

est, quam realis ratio, neque veritates possibilitatum et necessitaturn (seu negatarum in opposito possibilitatum) aliquid efficerent nisi possibilitates fundarentur in re actu existente.

Io

Io

 

31. 1. There is a ground in nature why something exists rather than nothing.

 

This is a consequence of the great principle that nothing exists without a ground, just as there also must be a ground why this exists rather than something else.

 

 T H E END O F P H I L O S O P H Y

 

Metaphysics a s H i s t o r y o f Being

 

3. H o c a u t e m E n s o p o r t e t necessarium esse, alioqui causa r u r s u s extra i p s u m quaerenda esset c u r i p s u m existat potius q u a m n o n existat, c o n t r a H y p o t h e s i n . E s t scilicet E n s illud ultima ratio R e r u m , e t u n o vocabulo solet appellari D E U S .

 

8, Sed quia a h a aliis incompatibilia s u n t , s e q u i t u r q u a e d a m possibilia n o n pervenire ad existendum, s u n t q u e alia aliis incompatibilia, n o n t a n t u m respectu ejusdem temporis, sed e t in universum, quia i n praesentibus f u t u r a involvuntur.

9, Interim e x conflictu o m n i u m possibilium existentiam exigentium h o c saltem sequitur, u t Existat ea r e r u m series, p e r q u a m p l u r i m u m existit, seu series o m n i u m possibilium maxima.

10, Haec etiam series sola est determinata, u t e x lineis recta, e x angulis

 

4. Est e r g o causa c u r Existentia praevaleat non-Existentiae, seu Ens necess a r i u m est Existentificans.

5. Sed q u a e causa facit u t aliquid existat, seu u t possibilitas exigat existentiam, facit etiam u t o m n e possibile habeat c o n a t u m ad Existentiam, c u m ratio restrictionis ad certa possibilia in universali reperiri n o n possit.

 

6. I t a q u e dici potest O m n e p o s s i b i l e Existiturire, p r o u t scilicet f u n d a t u r in E n t e necessario actu existente, s i n e q u o nulla est via q u a possibile perveniret ad a c t u m .

 

rectus, e x figuris m a x i m e capax, n e m p e circulus vel sphaera. E t u t i videmus liquida s p o n t e n a t u r a e colligi i n g u t t a s sphaericas, ita i n natura universi series maxima capax existit. 11. Existit e r g o perfectissimum, c u m nihil aliud perfectio [missing i n G e r hardt] sit q u a m q u a n t i t a s realitatis. 12. P o r r o perfectio n o n i n sola materia collocanda est, seu i n r e p l e n t e t e m p u s e t spatiurn, cujus q u o c u n q u e m o d o e a d e m fuisset quantitas, sed in forma seu varietate.

 

7. V e r u m h i n c n o n s e q u i t u r o m n i a possibilia existere: s e q u e r e t u r s a n e si

o m n i a possibiliaessent compossibilia.

 

2. This ground ought to be in some real being or cause. For a cause is nothing else than a real ground, and the truths of possibilities and necessities (or

 

Io

Io

 

negativities in the opposition of possibilities) would not produce anything unless the possibilities were grounded in an actually existing thing.

3. But this being must be necessary; otherwise, a ground would again have to

 

8. But because some possibles are incompatible with others, it follows that

 

be sought why it exists rather than not--contrary to our hypothesis. That being is, of course, the ultimate ground of things and is usually designated by the one word GOD.

4. Therefore there is a cause why existence prevailsover nonexistence, that is, necessary being is that which causes toexist (existent;Fcans).

 

i

Io

 

certain possibles do not attain existence. Moreover, some possibles are incompatible with others not only in regard to occurring at the same time, but also, in general, because future possibles are involved in present ones.

9. Nevertheless, from the conflict of all the possibles demanding existence,

 

this at least follows, that there exists that series of things by which the maximum could exist, that is, the maximal series of all possibles.

10. Only this series is determined, so that of lines straight ones are determi-

 

5. But this cause which makes something to exist, or some possibility to demand existence, also makes every possible to have a striving for existence, since, in general, a reason for restricting to only some possibles cannot be found.

6. Thus every possible can be said to strive to exist (existiturire) according as it is

 

nate; of angles, a right one; of figures, one with greatest capacity, to be sure, a circle or a sphere. And as we see liquids collect according to the will of nature in spherical drops, so in the nature of the universe the series of maximal capacity came to be.

11. Therefore the most perfect came to be since perfection [missing in Ger-

 

grounded in a necessary being actually existing, without which there is no way for a possible to become actual.

7. Still it does not follow from this that all possibles exist. It would follow, by all means, ifall possibles werecompossible.

 

hardt] is nothing else than quantity of reality.

12.

 

However, perfection is not to be placed in matter alone, that is, in filling time and space, whose quantity would be in whatever way the same, but in form or variety.

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

13. U n d e jam consequitur materiam n o n ubique similem esse, sed per formas reddi dissimilarem, alioqui n o n tantum obtineretur varietatis q u a n t u m posset. U t taceam quod alibi demonstravi, nulla alioqui diversa phaenomena esseextitura. 14. Sequitur etiam eam praevaluisse seriem, per quam plurimum oriretur distinctae cogitabilitatis.

 

Io

 

Metaphysics as History of Being

19. Itaque cum nobis aliqua displicet in serie rerum, id oritur ex defectu intellectionis. Neque enim possibile est ut omnis Mens omnia distincte intelligat, e t partes tantum alias prae aliis observantibus, non potest apparere Harmonia i n toto.

20. Ex his consequens est, in Universo etiam justitiam observari, cum Justitia nihil aliud sit quam ordo seu perfectio circa Mentes. 21. Et Mentium maxima habetur ratio, quia per ipsas q u a m maxima varietas in quam minimo spatio obtinetur. 22. Et dici potest Mentes esse primarias Mundi unitates, proximaque simulacra entis primi, quia rationes distincte percipiunt necessarias veritates, id est rationes quae movere E n s primum e t universum formare debuerunt.

 

IS. Porro distincta cogitabilitas dat ordinem rei e t pulchritudinem cogitanti. Est enim ordo nihil aliud quam relatio plurium distinctiva. E t confusio

est, c u m plura quidem adsunt, sed non est ratio quodvis a quovis distinguendi.

 

16. H i n c tolluntur atomi, e t in universum corpora, i n quibus nulla est ratio quamvis partem distinguendi a quavis.

17. Sequiturque in universum, M u n d u m esse kosmon, plenum ornatus, seu ita factum ut maximesatisfaciat intelligenti.

 

18. Voluptas enim intelligentis nihil aliud est quam perceptio pulchritudinis, ordinis, perfectionis. E t omnis dolor continet aliquid inordinati sed respective ad percipientem, c u m absoluteomnia sint ordinata.

 

23. Prima etiam causa summae est Bonitatis, nam d u m quantum plurimum perfectionis producit i n rebus, simul etiam q u a n t u m plurimum voluptatis mentibus largitur, c u m voluptas consistat in perceptione perfectionis (instead of: perceptionis).

order, perfection. And every pain contains something of disorder, but only with respect to the perceiver, since absolutely all things are ordered.

 

13. Whence it follows that matter is not everywhere uniform, but becomes diversified through forms; otherwise, not as much variety as possible would obtain. To pass over in silence what I have demonstrated elsewhere-no diverse phenomena would otherwise appear.

14. It follows also that that series prevailed by which there emerges the

 

19. And so when something dissatisfiesus in theseries of things, it arises from

 

a defect in the intellect. It is impossible for every mind to understand all things distinctly, and the harmony of the whole cannot be seen by those who observe only some parts rather than others. 20. It is a consequence of this that justice is observed in the universe, since justice is nothing but the order or perfection that obtains in respect to minds.

21. And the greatest ground belongs to minds, because through them is

 

greatest possibility of thinkingof things asdistinct.

15. Further, the possibility of thinking of things as distinct gives order to the

 

thing and beauty to the thinker. For order is nothing but the distinctive relation between many things, and confusion arises when there are many things, but noground for distinguishinganything from anythingelse. 16. Hence atoms are done away with and, in general, bodies in which there is noground fordistinguishingany part from any other.

17. And it follows, in general, that the world is a cosmos, fully adorned, that is,

 

obtained as much variety in as little space as possible. 22. And it can be said that minds are the primary unities of the world and the closest images of prime being, because they perceive grounds distinctly as necessary truths, that is, grounds which were bound to move prime being and to form the universe. 23. The first cause is of the highest goodness, for, while it produces as much perfection as possible in things, it also bestows as much pleasure as possible

 

so made as togive the most satisfaction to the perceiver. 18. For the pleasure of the perceiver is nothing but the perception of beauty,

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

24. Usque adeo ut mala ipsa serviant ad majus bonum, et quod dolore:

reperiuntur in Mentibus, necesse sit proficere ad majores voluptat

 

Io

 

(N. 1 1 and n. 2 3 are corrected following the manuscript.)

 

-

 

on minds, since pleasure consists in the perception of perfection (inste,. of: perception).

24. In order that evils themselves may serve the greater good, and becaust

 

Sketchesfor a Hirtory of Beingas Metaphysics

 

disappointments are found in minds, it is necessary to advance to highel pleasures.

 

TWO

 

Aletheia, barely presencing and not returning to the origin, but rather going forth to mere unconcealedness, comes under the yoke of the idea. 2. Viewed from the arche, the subjugation of aletheia stems from a release of beings to presence thus beginning. 3. T h e subjugation of aletheia is the preeminence of appearing and showing itself of the idea; the hen as phainotaton. 4. T h e precedence of the idea brings the ti estin along with the ezdos to the position of authoritative Being. Being is primarily whatness. We must consider how whatness as exclusive Being (idea as ontos on) gives more room to being itself, the on nominally conceived, than to the on verbally conceived. T h e undecidedness of beings and Being in the on, and its ambiguity. 5. T h e precedence of whatness brings the precedence of beings themselves in what they are. T h e precedence of beings establishes Being as koinon in terms of the hen. T h e eminent character of metaphysics is decided. T h e one as unifying unity becomes authoritative for subsequent determination of Being. 6. As authoritative Being, whatness usurps the realm of Being, namely Being in the primal determination lying before the distinc1.

 

'

i!l

Io

 

Il

 

Io

 

~1

 

Io

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY tion of what and that, which preserves for Being the fundamental characteristic of originating and emerging and presencing, thus of that which subsequently appears as thatness (hoti estin), but first and only in contrast to the precedence of whatness (idea). T h u s the prote ousia determined by Aristotle is precisely no longer the primal presencing of Being. Accordingly, the later existentia and existence can never reach back to the original essential fullness of Being, not even when it is thought in its Greek origin. We must consider how the that of the existentia never again attains the esti (eon) gar einai. 7. T h e ambiguity of the eon and on, not thought grammatically. What the nominal (beings themselves) and the verbal (Being) means when thought primally. H o w the ambiguity of the on includes the distinction. 8. T h e transformation of Being to certainty stems from the criterion of whatness. 9. T h e essence of thatness (reality) which remains taken for granted in its essential character finally permits the equation of unconditional certainty with absolute reality. 10. All events in the history of Being which is metaphysics have their beginning and ground in the fact that metaphysics leaves and must leave the essence of Being undecided, in that it remains indifferent from the beginning to a regarding of what is worthy of question in favor of saving its own essence, and indeed in the indifference of not-knowing.

 

Sketchesfor a History of Being as Metaphysics respect to the will as a faculty of the soul. T h e will must rather be brought to essential unity with appearance: idea, re-praesentatio, becoming evident, portraying itself; attaining itseK transcending itself; and thus "having itself;" and thus "being." 2. T h e necessity of the system as the constitution of subiectity, that is, of Being as the beingness of beings, lies in the essential constituents of the will understood in this way. 3. T h e system is a system only as an absolute system. 4. Hence the two characteristics of modern metaphysics' essential completion: (1) the manner in which the concept of philosophy is determined by the absolute system; (2) the manner in which the system is distorted and negated in the most extreme completion of metaphysics by Nietzsche.

 

OBJECTIVITY-TRANSCENDENCE-UNITY-BEIN

(Critique o Pure Reason, section 16) f T h e system: Unity-ousia-hen as unity of "standing together" before consciousness and for consciousness. Standing together determines the essence of unity. However, unity itself must be determined and questioned in its essence in the question about the truth of Being. Co-agito, legein, gathering: Hen and Logos. Together: collected-present. Standing: constancy. Representation and letting stand together. Representation as "certain," certum, as securing. Certainty as guarantee of stability. System. Then what does the Kantian "I think" mean? Something like: I represent something as something, that is, I let something stand together before me. Unity is necessary for standing together and is in essence determined by it. Unity is the condition (of synthesis and connection); but its

 

1. In the essential change of truth as veritas to certitudo, Being is prefigured as the representedness of self-representing in which the essence of subiectity develops. T h e simplest name for the determination of the beingness of beings in preparation here is the will, will as willing-itsel$ T h e essential fullness of the will cannot be determined with

 

 T H E E N D OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Sketches for a History of Being as Metaphysics

1~

 

11

~l;

 

essence is itself conditioned by the essence of "standing together' (section 16): that standing together presences at all, that Being presences as hen and not nothing. Together-para. Stand: place, posit, ponere; sistere: Sistence, Position. Standing-there-stasis. Appearance-eidos, idea. But everything already in the presence, ousia, of the ego cogit0 cogitationes.

 

Since the fifteenth century, the word, "object" has had the meaning of: opposition. For Luther, object means: the opposed "status": the Jewish status and the Christian status: "to adopt the opposing status." Since the eighteenth century, the word has been taken as the translation of obiectum. A quarrel begins as to whether one should say ob-ject or ob-stacle. Ob-ject and representation: re-praesentare. For a carpenter the wood is the object, that is, "what he works againstm-when he functions as cause. With regard to the ontic-ontological distinction of beings and Being, what is objective is that in the object which has color, extension, etc.; what is objective: what constitutes its standing against as such.

 

One thinks Being as objectivity, and then tries from there to find beings in themselves. Only one forgets to question and to say what one means by "in being." What "is" Being? Being-unquestioned and a matter of course and thus unthought and uncomprehended in a truth which has long since been forgotten, and is groundless. Being is beingness; beingness as ousia is presence, continual presence with its space-time forgotten. Presence grounds the para, the "with." T h e "with" supports and bears the "together" and the "together with"; the latter can, of course, be taken for unity and one, but at the same time remain unperceived and forgotten in its true essence. Stability grounds constancy together with presence (verbal) as objectivity when the "ob" becomes essential through the re-praesentatio. When does this happen? With the insurrection of the subiectum qua ego as res cogitans qua certum. Thus unity comes as the changed form of ousia, determined by truth as certainty, to the relation to representational thinking which necessarily looks with regard and as regard representing toward unity, and which is the "I connect" in the manner of representation. Primally, however, the hen is understood neither in terms of "I think" nor in terms of idea, but rather from nous(Parmenides) and logos in Heraclitus's sense as the gathering that reveals and secures.

OBJECTIVITY AND REFLEXION NEGATIVITY AND

 

1

 

~

 

1

 

Io

 

111

 

~

 

~

 

Io

 

Il

 

REFLEXION

 

Io

 

How does objectivity take on the character of constituting the essence of beings as such?

 

The question about the essential origin of the "object" in general. That is the question about the truth of beings in modern metaphysics. (Unity and objectivity; essence of unity, ousia.) Hegel's determination of experience as allowing the new true object to originate shows the formulation of the object's concept in the absolute transcendental sense. Hence this is the place for a necessary reflection upon the essence of the object in general. (The misunderstanding of the "theory of the object.")

 

~1

 

?'I1

 

Io

 

'

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY Object in the sense of object: Only when man becomes subject, that is, where the subject becomes the ego and the ego becomes the ego cogito, only where this cogitare is understood in its essence as "original synthetic unity of transcendental apperception," only where the culmination for "logic" is reached (in truth as the certainty of the "I think"), only there is the essence of the object revealed in its objectivity. Only there is it at the same time possible and inevitable to understand this objectivity itself as "the new true object," and to think it as unconditional. Decisive: Kant-in that doctrine which is unobtrusively contained in a side remark in the Critique o Pure Reason; an addition, f but filled with essential insight and critical dialogue with Leibniz and all previous metaphysics as Kant himself views it (cf. Critique o Pure Reason, "Supplement" to the transcendental analytic: "Of the f Amphiboly of the Concepts of Reflection"). "Reflexion," understood in the light of the history of Being, of human being: shining back into aletheia without aletheia itself being experienced and grounded and coming to "being" (Wesen). T h e uncanny element of the shining-back (re-flexion) of what shows itself. Man's settling down in one of his essential places. Reflexion-certainty, certainty-self-consciousness.

 

Sketchesfor a History of Being as Metaphysics reason reflexion is a fundamental characteristic of concept formation. "Concept": What is represented as such, thinking, representing; that is, presenting itself. What is represented in the "I think." Thus we must distinguish at first and in general: 1. Reflexion which is already active in the re-praesentatio and is not expressed; 2. expressed, explicitly accomplished reflexion. Explicitly accomplished reflexion: a. As logical (analytic) analysis, comparison (without relation to the object as such): T h e leaf is green. b. Objective comparison as the connection (nexus) of representations among themselves in relation to the object: T h e sun warms the stone. c. T h e transcendental condition of the possibility of b. When objects are to be judged apriori, that is, in a Kantian manner: when something is to be decided upon as to its objectivity, the object is explicitly re-presented and presented to the faculty o representation. T h e object as such stands in the f unity of intuition and concept. Their unification is the condition of the positing and the constancy of the "over against."

 

Understood in advance as a fundamental characteristic of representational thinking, of the re-praesentatio. Reflexion is bendingback, and as such it is the explicitly accomplished presentation of what is present; explicitly, that is, in such a way that what is present is presented to the representer. T h e bending-back, putting-back, that is, the representation of what is represented which presents itself in advance to itself, in which what is represented is represented as this and that, and is. T h e "what" itself in its sameness and positedness, constancy. For this reason reflexion strives for the identical, and for this

 

Reflexion, object, and subjectivity belong together. Only when reflexion is experienced as such, that is, as the relation to beings, is Being first determinable as objectivity. T h e experience of reflexion as this relation presupposes, however, that the relation to beings in general is experienced as repraesentatio, as re-presenting, making-present. This, however, can only become historical (understood in the manner of the history of Being) when idea has become idea, that is, perceptio. But the change from truth as correspondence to truth as certainty underlies this, the adaequatio still being preserved. Cer-

 

 -

 

T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY Sketches for a History of Being as Metaphysics

 

tainty as self-ensuring (willing oneself); the iustitia as the justification of the relation to beings and their first cause, and thus the belongingness to beings; the iustitia in the sense of the reformation and Nietzsche's concept of justice as truth. Repraesentatio is grounded in rejlexio in accordance with its essence. Hence the essence of objectivity as such first becomes evident where the essence of thinking is recognized and explicitly enacted as "I think something," that is, as reflexion.

 

grounded in the fundamental position of the "I think." This "intuition" in Kant's sense can never be equated with the precedence of aletheia, but only with the precedence of idea and the of aletheia to homoiosis through the precedence of the idea, as the germ of development of representing in the sense of making present.

 

1

 

Io

Io

 

BEING-REALITY-WILL

Being as reality-reality as will. Will-as self-effectuation striving toward itself in accordanrwith a re-presentation of itself (the will to will). (All of this pre ences, shut off from itself, in the opening of Being.) T h e will first becomes essential in the actualitas where the ens actu is determined by the agere as cogitare, since this cogito is me cogitare, self-conscious-being, where consciousness as knowingness is essentially presenting-to-oneself. Will as fundamental characteristic of reality. T h e volitional basic trait in re-presentation itself as the perceptio; hence perceptio is in itself appetitus, co-agitare. T h e will releases itself in truth as certainty. It is brought to the origin by this essence of truth. Will is effecting which plans something according to what is re-presented. Releasing itself in certainty from the misjudgment of the essence of truth; this misjudgment is the deeper unknowing. T h e will (as essential and fundamental characteristic of beingness) has its essential origin in the intrinsic unknowingness of the essence of truth as the truth of Being. For this reason, metaphysics remains the truth of the Being of beings in the sense of reality as will. This unknowingness, however, rules in the form of the omnicalculation of certainty. T h e will has never had the origin as its own. It has always already intrinsically abandoned it by forgetting. T h e most profound oblivion is not-recollecting.

 

THE TRANSCENDENTAL

T h e transcendental is not the same as the "a priori," but is rather what determines the object as object a priori, objectivity. Objectivity is meant in the sense of transcendence. This word then means that something in the object itself goes beyond that object by preceding it, in representing. Transcendence is grounded in "reflexion." Reflexion is transcendental in its true essence, that is, it accomplishes transcendence and thus conditions it in general. T h e essential and constant re-servation of thinkability, that is, of the representability of something as the condition of all knowledge. I think something. (Cf. Critique of Pure Reason, B XXVI, Preface.)

 

~'

I I

 

,~

 

~11

 

Repraesentatio is grounded in rejlexio. But rejlexio is the essence of "thinking," if thinking itself is taken transcendentally as true re-presentation, bringing something as something before oneself, that is, intuition taken in the essential sense. Logic itself is related as transcendental logic to this original re-presentation-presence, presencing, and ousia. It is thus meaningless to pit thinking against intuition. Indeed, the precedence of "intuition," too, is and remains

 

~

 

~

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Sketches for a History of Being as Metaphysics

 

BEINGAND CONSCIOUSNESS

(Expressed in the Manner of the History of Being) Consciousness is self-consciousness, and self-consciousness is ego-consciousness or "wew-consciousness. T h e essential thing in this is the re-flexive, and in it the "I," "we," "self," the presentation-to-self and self-production. T h e will to insure in the overpowering of everything. T h e essential thing is "I will myself." "Consciousness" (as will of the will) must itself now be experienced with regard to the truth of beings (as beingness)-as appropriating of Being. Desolation. Consciousness is that appropriating in which Being gives itself to truth, that is, leaves truth to beings and beingness, and beingness expropriates truth. T h e appropriation of expropriation and of directing beings into mere beingness.

 

REALITY WILL AS

(Kant's Concept of Being) Will according to Kant: to act in accordance with concepts. For Kant, Being means: 1. Objectivity-certainty as representedness of experience; in this: a. certainty of synthesis 6. impressionableness of sensibility, both as reality (cf. "The Postulates of All Empirical Thought"). 2. Reality of freedom-as thing in itself, that is, will. 3. Cf. 16, impressionableness of sensibility; having an effecteffectiveness. T o consider whether and how these determinations of Being are thought in a unified way, or whether reality (cf. "The Postulates of All Empirical Thought") can from the beginning remain precisely unthought, and how nevertheless ontology can persist as transcendental philosophy.

 

How the concept of Being of rationalism (ens ~ e r t u m - ~ b j ~ ~ tivity) and of empiricism (impressio-reality) meet in the determination of the reality of what is real. Effectiveness, however, not formal and general, but in the original manner of the history of Being. Effectiveness and accomplishment: function. Effectiveness and presence; givenness and impressionability. Kant's category of "reality" in its essential ambiguity (related to sensibility and thingness at the same time). Effecting and will, vis, actus. Everywhere the lack of questioning Being. Most evident in Kant's definition: Being (is) "merely position." T o begin with, the thesis means: Being (is) merely the positing of the copula between subject and predicate. Secondly, the thesis means: Being (in the sense of human being and existence) is the pure positing of the thing in departing from its concept. Finally, the thesis means: Being, the "is" of the copula, aims in the judgment of experience at the positing of the object as a real object (Critique o Pure Reason, second edition, section 19). f In the negative form, Kant's thesis about Being as "merely position" means: Being is neither a real predicate with content nor any predicate at all of any thing or object whatever. Kant's thesis about Being-an ontotheological one, expressed in the context of the question of God's existence in the sense of the summum ens qua ens realissimum. What was without question for Kant is for us worthy of question: the essential origin of L'position"in terms of letting what is present lie present in its presence. Ponere (posit, place, gather) coming from: thesis, repraesentatio (re-presenting), and legein (bringing to appear in a revealing way).

 

Aletheia (apeiron, logos, hen-arche). Revealing as the order at the start.

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY Physis, emergence (going back to itself). Ousia, presencing, unconcealedness. Idea, perceivability (agathon), causality. Energeia, workness, assembly, en-echeia to telos. Hypokeimenon, lie present (from ousia), ergon. (Presence-stability-constancy-aei.) Hyparchein, presencing which rules from what already lies present. Subiectum. Actualitas: beings-the real-reality creator-ens creatum causa prima (ens a se). Certitudo-res cogitans. Vis-monas (perceptio-uppetitus), exigentia essentiae. Objectivity. Freedom will-representedness practical reason. Will-as absolute knowledge: Hegel. As will of love: Schelling. Will to power-eternal recurrence: Nietzsche. Action and Organization-pragmatism. T h e will to will. Machination (Enframing).

 

Io

 

Sketchesfor a History of Being as Metaphysl that does not destroy, but rather chokes what is primal in organizing and ordering. Being's abandonment contains the undecided factor of whether the unconcealment of this concealment, and thus the more primal Origin, is already opening u p in this abandonment as an extreme of the concealment of Being. At such a time span of the undecidedness, in which the completion of metaphysics develops and claims human being for the "superman," man seizes upon the rank of what is truly real in itself. T h e reality of what is real, long since characterized as existence, allots this distinction to man. Man is the truly existent, and existence is determined in terms of human being whose essence has been decided by the beginning of modern metaphysics. Since thinking, on the edge of the time span of undecidedness in the history of Being, gropes its way toward a first recollection in Being, it must at the same time go through the dominance of human being and leave it aside. T h e preeminence of existence in the sense of reality as being-aself, prefigured in the first completion of metaphysics with Schelling, reaches a peculiar narrowing after being deflected from its way by Kierkegaard, who is neither a theologian nor a metaphysician and yet the essential element of both. T h e fact that the transformation of reality to the self-certainty of the ego cogito is determined directly by Christianity, and the fact that the narrowing of the concept of existence is indirectly determined by Christian factors only proves how Christian faith adopted the fundamental trait of metaphysics and brought metaphysics to Western dominance in this form.

 

T h e completion of metaphysics sets beings in the abandonment of Being. Being's abandonment of beings is the last reflection of Being as the concealment of unconcealment in which all beings of any sort as such are able to appear. Being's abandonment contains the undecided factor of whether beings persist in their precedence. In the future, this means the question of whether beings undermine and uproot every possibility of the origin in Being, and thus continue to be busy with beings, but also move towards the desolation

 

Effecting, and thus causalitas (agathon, as what makes possible), lies in "reality" which becomes the dominant basic characteristic of the beingness of beings. Effecting lies in "reality," and effecting contains in itself representation and striving which act in virtue of

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Sketches for a History of Being as Metaphys

 

their own unity. T h e effecting thus determined is a self-effecting. Herein lies the possible claim of self-ensuring, certainty as selfcertainty. Where there is reality, there is will; where there is "will," there is a self-willing; where there is a self-willing, there are possibilities of the essential development of the will as reason, love, power. When and how does the essence of will become essential to reality? T h e fact that reality at last enters the essence of will in the completion of metaphysics-and "will" is not to be thought "psychologically," but on the contrary psychology is to be defined by the essence of self-effecting-bears witness to the decisiveness of the essential development of beingness from the pro-gression of Beings to beingness. T h e primal progression does, however, leave the origin behind as ungrounded, and can therefore place great importance upon organizing itself as pro-gress and going forth. In the essence of will of beingness as reality, there is concealed machination (poiesis), essentially never accessible to metaphysics, in which energeia still has resonance from its primal essential traits in which the progression from the first origin (aletheia) takes its decisive beginning which predetermines everything. Energeia is, however, at the same time the last preservation of the essence of physis, and thus a belonging to the origin.

 

What metaphysics generally calls existentia, existence, reality, human being is 1. ousia of the hypokeimenon kath'hauto, that is, of the hekaston; the prote ousia; presencing as dwelling of what is actual (Aristotle). 2. This prote ousia is understood as energeia of the on, as tode ti on, the presencing of what is produced and set up, workness. T h e broadest name for einai as presencing, which at the same time explains its Greek interpretation, is hyparchein. There hypo-keisthai, what already lies present, is thought together with arche, the ruling

 

origin; hyparchein means to rule while already lying present, "ruling forthwthought in a Greek way as to presence of itself. 3. Energeia is reinterpreted to mean actualitas of the actus. Agere as facere, creare. T h e pure essence of actualitas is the actuspurus as the existentia of the ens to whose essentia existentia belongs (medieval theology). Accomplishment as effecting what is effected, not allowing to presence in unconcealment, characterizes the actus. 4. In accordance with the change of veritas to certitude, actualitas is understood as actus of the ego cogito, as percipere, repraesentare. T h e precedence of the subiectum in the sense of the ego (Descartes); the existere as the esse of the ego sum; the repraesentare (percipere) contrasted with the noein as idein, and this contrasted with the noein of Parmenides. From Being as presence, Being comes to be as representedness in the subject. 5. T h e repraesentare as perceptio-appetitus in the sense of the vis primitiva activa is the actualitas of every subiectum in the old sense, and determines the essence of substance as monad. T h e corresponding distinction of phenomenon and phainesthai. Existentia is now exigentia essentiae; its principium the perfectio, perfectio is gradus essentiae; essentia, however, nisus ad existendum. T h e Scholastic distinction of potentia and actus, which itself represents a reinterpretation of the Aristotelian distinction dynamis-energeia, is overcome (Leibniz). 6. Existence as actualitas, reality, effectedness and effectingness, becomes the objectivity of experience, and thus a modality along with possibility and necessity. 7 . T h e unconditional certainty of the will knowing itself as absolute reality (spirit, love). Existence as Being is determined from the "real" distinction of the Being of beings according to ground of existence and existence of the ground. Because the will constitutes the essence of Being, the distinction belongs to willing itself: the will of the ground and the will of reason.

 

 T H E E N D OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Sketches for a History o f Being as Metaph3

 

Existence: becoming revealed, bringing oneself to oneself, selfbeing in self-becoming, against and opposing the ground. Becoming "contradictory" in itself (Schelling). 8. Existence in Schelling's sense is narrowed by Kierkegaard to the being who "is" in the contradiction of temporality and eternity, to man who wills to be himself. Existing as faith, that is, trust in the reality of the real being which man himself is. Faith as revelation before God. Trust in the reality that God became man. Faith as being a Christian in the sense of becoming a Christian. 9. Existence in Kierkegaard's sense, only without the essential relation to Christian faith, being a Christian. Being a self as personality in virtue of communication with others. Existence in the relationship to "Transcendence" (K. Jaspers). 10. Existence-sometimes used in Being and Time as ecstatic perduring the opening of the there of human being. Perduring the truth of Being, grounded upon the explicit grounding of the ontological difference, that is, the distinction between beings and Being (outside of all metaphysics and existential philosophy). 11. How the distinction of essentia and existentia disappears in Nietzsche's metaphysics, why it must disappear in the end of metaphysics, how nevertheless in just this way the greatest distance from the origin is attained. But disappearance can only be shown by trying to make the distinction visible: will to power as essentia; eternal recurrence of the same as existentia (cf. "Nietzsche's Metaphysics").

 

Christians through Kierkegaard (existence-being a Christian) (faith-theology). 3. T h e adoption of Kierkegaard's concept of existence in "existential philosophy" (K. Jaspers). Existence: being-a-self-communication-metaphysics. 4. Existence as a character of human being in Being and Time (History of Being). Here neither Kierkegaard's concept nor that of existential philosophy is at stake. Rather, existence is thought by returning to the ecstatic character of human being1 with the intention of interpreting being-open2 in its eminent relation to the truth of Being. T h e occasional use of the concept of existence is determined solely by this question. T h e question serves only to prepare for an overcoming of metaphysics. All this is outside of existential philosophy and existentialism. Thus it is profoundly different from Kierkegaard's passion which is at bottom theological. But it does remain in the essential critical dialogue with metaphysics. In what sense the concept of the existentielle can and must appear with Schelling for the first time. T h e existentielle, that is, what exists viewed with reference to its existence, that is, however, as an existing being; more precisely, beings, thought in terms of their existing, as existing beings. One must pay attention to the shift in Schelling's terminology here: ground-existence existence-existing being.

 

SCHELLING KIERKEGAARD AND

1. T h e emphatic use of the concept of existence in Schelling's distinction of existence of the ground and ground of existence (Being as will). 2. T h e restriction of this concept of existence to the faith of

 

Existence: being a self--subjectivity (the will of reason, ego cogito) revelation contradictiondistinction

1.

 

Dasein.

 

2. Da-sein.

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Sketches for a History of Being as Metaphys;

 

"pas~ion"-L'dri~e))-LLkn~~ing will1'-"becoming" But for Kierkegaard: 1. restricted to man, only he exists. 2. Existence-interest in existence, reality. 3 . This interest is not a representation, but faith in . . . , committing oneself to what is real, letting oneself be concerned with what is real. 4. Faith in another, not as relation to a doctrine and its truth, but as relation to the true as the real, to concresce with it, concretely. Existence in the modern sense. 5. Faith that God existed as man, infinitely interested-faith as being a Christian, that is, becoming a Christian. Lack of faith as sin.

 

EXISTENCE AND

 

THE

 

EXISTENTIELL.

 

"Willing is primal being." All Being is the same as existing: existence. But existence is existence of the ground. Existence and ground of existence belong to Being. This distinction belongs to Being as a "real" one. Being itself is of such a nature that beings as such divide themselves. This distinction lies in the essence of willing. The distinction: will of the ground and will of reason. How so? T h e will in willing is reason. Schelling's "distinction" signifies an opposition (strife) which structures and rules all essence (beings in their beingness), all of this always based upon subjectivity. Primal being-is will. Being (not yet being-a-being) closedness. A being (substantive, verbal-transitive): the self. being-in-itself.

 

T h e existentielle means this: In his humanity man is not only related to what is real through ways of behavior, but as an existing being he is concerned about himself, that is, about these relations and what is real. Reality is of such a nature that everything real preempts man everywhere as effector and an effecting being, as a co-worker and something effected. Taken with an apparent historical indifference, the existentielle is not necessarily to be understood in a Christian way as with Kierkegaard, but with every respect to putting man to work as an effector of what is real. T h e echo which existential elements have found in the last decades is grounded in the essence of the reality which as will to power has made man into an instrument of making (production, effecting). This essence of Being can remain veiled in spite of Nietzsche, and even for Nietzsche himself. Hence the existentielle admits of manifold interpretations. Its echo and predominance and the historically impossible pairing of Nietzsche and Kierkegaard are grounded in the fact that the existentielle is merely the intensification of the role of anthropology within metaphysics in its completion. T h e manifold forms of the existentielle in poetry, in thinking, in action, in faith, in production. They can only be seen when the existentielle itself is experienced as the completion of the animal rationale. And this is possible only in the manner of the history of Being. "World view" and the "existentielle." "Metaphysics" and "anthropology." Being as beingness and man as animal rationale. T h e exposition of the narrowing down of the nature of existence starts with Schelling's distinction of "ground and existence." T o be shown: 1 . How the usual distinction of essentia and existentia is hidden even behind this distinction.

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

2. Why this distinction gets formulated in peculiar versions which are even contrary to each other (for example, "Being and beings"; "existence and the existing being"; where "existence" now stands for "ground" and the existence mentioned before is formulated as the "existing being." This term is actually more accurate. It expresses the rank of realization and the producer, self-ensuring as effecting and will). 3. How Kierkegaard adopts this distinction by narrowing the concept of existence to the being a Christian of Christian existence. This should not be taken to mean that the nonexisting is the nonreal. If only man is the existing, precisely God is what is absolutely real and reality.

 

THREE

 

R ecullection inMetaphysics

 

__

 

Recollection in the history of Being thinks history as the arrival, always remote, of the perdurance of truth's essence. Being occurs primally in this essence. Recollection helps the remembrance of the truth of Being by allowing the following to come to mind: T h e essence of truth is at the same time the truth of essence. Being and truth belong to each other just as they belong intertwining to a still concealed rootedness in the origin whose origination opening up remains that which comes. That which is original occurs in advance of all that comes. Although hidden, it thus comes toward historic man as pure coming. It never perishes, it is never something past. Thus we also never find what is Original in the historical retrospect of what is past, but rather only in remembrance which thinks at the same time upon presencing Being (what has been in being), and upon the destined truth of Being. At times recollection in history can be the only viable way to what is primal for the mindfulness practiced by the perduring thinking of the history of Being. Recollection in metaphysics as a necessary epoch of the history of Being gives us food for thought: that and how Being determines the truth of beings in each case; that and how Being opens out a realm of projection for the explanation of beings in terms of this determination; that and how such a determination first attunes thinking to the claim of Being, and compels a thinker to speak of Being in virtue of this attunement.

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Recollection in Metaphysics

 

Io

 

Recollection of the history of Being in metaphysics is a bestowal which explicitly and uniquely gives the relation of Being and man to awareness to be pondered. It requires the courage for a response to the claim which either confronts the dignity of Being or else contents itself with beings. Recollection of the history of Being entrusts historical humanity with the task of becoming aware that the essence of man is released to the truth of Being before any human dependency on powers and forces, predestinations and tasks. Hence he remains left out of his essence for a long time, as one let into the insurrection of production within Being's realm of opening u p in the sense of unconditional objectification. Being first lets powers arise, but also lets them sink into what is without essence, together with their impotence. Recollection in the history of Being continually entrusts the essence of man to Being, not individual man, but man at home in his decisive character, in order that Being may tower in the openedness of its own dignity and have a home in beings cared for by man's nature. Only from human being, that is, from the manner in which man grants the word of response to the claim of Being, can a reflection of its dignity shine forth to Being. In the timespan when Being delivers primordiality to the Open, and lets the purity of its freedom in relation to itself, and thus consequently its independence, too, be known and preserved, Being needs the reflection of a radiance of its essence in truth. This need is not the restlessness of a lack. It is the self-containedness of the wealth of the simple. As the simple, the Origin grants its decisiveness in a parting in which it approaches itself as what is granting, and thus allows pure needlessness to be once more in its own origination. This needlessness is itself a reflection of what is primal, taking place as the appropriation of truth. At times Being needs human being, and yet it is never dependent upon existing humanity. Humanity does stand in relationship to Being, since it is historical and knows and preserves beings as such. But human being's claim upon Being itself is not always

 

granted by Being as the gift through which mankind may have as its own the privilege of participating in the appropriation of the truth of Being. At such a time there sometimes arises from the claim of Being the attempt at a response in which mankind must sacrifice the individuals addressed who recollect Being, and thus think its history from the essential past. Recollection does not report on past opinions and representations about Being. It also does not trace the relations of their influence nor tell about standpoints within conceptual history. It is unconcerned with the progression and regression of a series of problems in themselves, which are supposed to constitute a history of problems. Because we only know, and only want to know, history in the context of historiography which explores and exposes elements of the past for the purpose of using them for the present, recollection in the history of Being also falls prey to the illusion that makes it appear to be conceptual historiography, and a one-sided and sporadic one at that. But when recollection of the history of Being names thinkers and pursues their thoughts, this thinking is the listening response which belongs to the claim of Being, as determination attuned by the voice of that claim. T h e thinking of thinkers is neither something going on in "heads" nor is it the product of such heads. One can always consider thought historiographically in accordance with such viewpoints, and appeal to the correctness of this consideration. However, one does not thus think thinking as the thinking of Being. Recollection of the history of Being returns to the claim of the soundless voice of Being and to the manner of its attuning. Thinkers are not reciprocally measured with regard to their accomplishments which deliver success for the progress of knowledge. Every thinker oversteps the inner limit of every thinker. But such overstepping is not "knowing it all," since it only consists in holding the thinker in the direct claim of Being, thus remaining within his limitation. This limitation consists in the fact that the

 

 Io

 

T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Io

 

Recollection in Metaphysi

 

thinker can never himself say what is most of all his own. It must remain unsaid, because what is sayable receives its determination from what is not sayable. What is most of all the thinker's own, however, is not his possession, but rather belongs to Being whose transmission thinking receives in its projects. But these projects only bear witness to the dwelling1 in what is transmitted. T h e historicity of a thinker (how he is claimed by Being for history and co-responds to this claim) is never measured by the historiographically calculable role which his opinions, always and of necessity misunderstood in his own time, play in their public circulation. T h e historicity of a thinker, which is not a matter of him but of Being, has its measure in the original loyalty of the thinker to his inner limitation. Not to know this inner limitation, not to know it thanks to the nearness of what is unsaid and unsayable, is the hidden gift of Being to the rare thinkers who are called to the path of thought. O n the other hand, historiographical calculation looks for the inner limitation of a thinker in the fact that he is not yet informed about things foreign to him which other and later thinkers accept as truth, sometimes only through his mediation. We are not speaking here of the psychology of philosophers, but solely of the history of Being. However, the fact that Being determines the truth of beings and attunes a thinking to the uniqueness of a Saying of Being through the presencing of truth at times, and determines a thinker in his determinacy from such a determination, the fact that in all of this Being appropriates its own truth previously and always primally and that this is the appropriating wherein Being presences-this can never be proved from the perspective of beings. It is also inaccessible to every explanation. Being in its history can only be perdured in that perdurance which re1. Befangnir. A word which easily has negative connotations (of being caught,

 

i

Io

 

imprisoned, inhibited) in German. But Heidegger explained that he intends no such negative connotation, only the meaning of remaining within what is transmitted.

 

leases the structure of human being to the relation to Being for the sole primal dignity of Being, so that it may continually endure, standing in the preservation of Being. What happens in the history of Being? We cannot ask in this manner, because there would then be an occurrence and something which occurs. But occurrence itself is the sole happening. Being alone is. What happens? Nothing happens if we are searching for something occurring in the occurrence. Nothing happens, Appropriation appropriates. Perduring the opening out, the origin takes the parting to itself. T h e appropriating origin is dignity as truth itself reaching into its departure. Dignity is what is noble which appropriates without needing effects. T h e noble of the worthy Appropriating of the origin is the unique release as Appropriation of freedom, which is unconcealment of concealment-because it belongs to the ground-less. T h e history of Being, which is solely Being itself, casts only a dim light into the supposedly sole transparency of the certainty of completed metaphysical knowledge. However, metaphysics is the history of Being as the progression out of the Origin. This progression allows the return to become a need, and allows recollection in the Origin to become a needful necessity. T h a t history of Being which is historically familiar as metaphysics has its essence in that a progression from the Origin occurs. In this progression Being releases itself to beingness and refuses the opening out of the Origin's originating. Beingness, starting as idea, begins the precedence of beings with regard to the essential character of truth whose essence itself belongs to Being. In that Being releases itself into beingness and withdraws its dignity in concealment, which is itself at the same time concealed, Being seems to leave the appearance of Being to beings. Since man is singled out within beings because he knows beings as beings and, knowing them, is related to them without, however, ever being able to know, that is, to preserve as a consequence of this distinction the ground of that distinction, man struggles for

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

manifold dominance in the area of beings left to themselves in the history of Being which is called metaphysics. Beings are what is real. Reality rescues its essence in effecting, which brings the knowing will as its own essence to authoritative effectiveness. Reality transposes its essence to the multiple forms of the will. T h e will produces itself in the exclusiveness of its egotism as the will to power. But in the essence of power there is hidden the utmost abandonment of Being to beingness. Through this abandonment, beingness becomes machination. O n the surface, machination appears in the form of the precedence of the actualization of what is planned and can be planned in the area of what is calculated as real. T h e precedence over Being of what is real as the only being is unconditional. Being appears only to be subjected to scorn each time. T h e name of this scorn is "abstraction."* T h e precedence of what is real furthers the oblivion of Being. Through this precedence, the essential relation to Being which is to be sought in properly conceived thinking is buried. In being claimed by beings, man takes on the role of the authoritative being. As the relation to beings, that knowledge is adequate which is used up by reification in accordance with the essential manner of beings, in the sense of the real as calculable and ensured. Knowledge thus becomes calculation. T h e sign of the degradation of thinking is the elevation of logistics to the rank of true logic. Logistics is the calculable organization of the unconditional lack of knowledge about the essence of thinking, provided that thinking, essentially thought, is that projecting knowledge which unfolds in virtue of Being in the preservation of truth's essence. T h e surrender in which Being abandons itself to the utmost deformation of essence of beingness (to "machination") is in a hidden way the self-suspension of the primal essence of Appropriation in the Origin which has not yet begun, not yet entered, its ground2. The meaning here is that the scornful attitude toward Being calls it an abstraction.

 

Io

 

Recollection in Metapbysic.

 

lessness. T h e progression of Being to beingness is that history of Being-called metaphysics-which remains just as essentially remote from the Origin in its start as in its finish. Thus metaphysics itself, too, that is, that thinking of Being which had to give itself the name "philosophy," can never bring the history of Being itself, that is, the Origin, to the light of its essence. T h e progression of Being to beingness is at the same time the primal refusal of an essential grounding of the truth of Being and the surrender in favor of beings of the precedence in the essential character of Being. T h e progression from the Origin does not relinquish that Origin. Otherwise beingness would not be a mode of Being. T h e progression can also do nothing about the refusal of the Origin. T h e primal veils itself in this refusal to the point of insufficiency. But in the progression the distinction of Being and beings enters the truth (openness) of Being undetermined in its turn, without explicitly entering its grounded structure. However, the distinction of Being and beings rescues itself immediately in the form of that distinction which alone co-responds to the beginning of metaphysics because it receives its structure from beings and from the distinction of beings and Being. Beings are. Their Being contains the truth that they are. T h e fact that beings are gives to beings the privilege of the unquestioned. From here the question arises as to what beings are. From the perspective of beings, whatness is thus the being first questioned. Here it becomes evident that Being determines itself only in the form of beingness and then through such determination itself only brings beings as such to presence. Only then is thatness explicitly distinguished from whatness (idea). T h e distinction which becomes familiar under the name of the difference of essentia and existentia in metaphysics, but hardly becomes visible in its own transformations, is itself grounded in the primal and true distinction of Being and beings, which is not grounded and is at the same time hidden. T h e primal distinction, however, is not an act which invades and coincides with what is factually undifferentiated of Being and

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Recollection in Metaphysics

 

beings. T h e distinction is primally rather the presencing of Being itself whose origination is Appropriation. T h e original distinction can never be reached by going back behind the distinction of essentia and existentia, which underlies all metaphysics and which has its core in the essential character of the existentia. O n the other hand, the metaphysical distinction itself-that means always, the distinction which structures and underlies all metaphysics-must first be experienced in its Origin, so that metaphysics becomes decisive as occurrence of the history of Being, and relinquishes the illusory form of a doctrine and an opinion, that is, of something produced by man. T h e history of Being is neither the history of man and of humanity, nor the history of the human relation to beings and to Being. T h e history of Being is Being itself, and only Being. However, since Being claims human being for grounding its truth in beings, man is drawn into the history of Being, but always only with regard to the manner in which he takes his essence from the relation of Being to himself and, in accordance with this relation, loses his essence, neglects it, gives it up, grounds it, or squanders it. T h e fact that man belongs to the history of Being only in the scope of his essence which is determined by the claim of Being, and not with regard to his existence, actions, and accomplishments within beings, signifies a restriction unique in its manner. This restriction can become evident as a distinction as often as Being itself allows what takes place to be known if man may venture his essence which has sunk into oblivion for him through the precedence of beings. In the history of Being, Appropriation makes itself known to humanity at first as a transformation of the essence of truth. This could give rise to the opinion that the essential character of Being might be dependent upon the dominance of the actual concept of truth which guides the manner of human representational thinking, and thus the thinking of Being. But the possibilities of the actual concepts of truth are delineated in advance by the manner of the

 

essence of truth and the prevailing of this essence. Opening out is itself a fundamental characteristic of Being, and not only its consequence. Recollection in the history of Being is a thinking ahead to the Origin, and belongs to Being itself. Appropriation grants the time from which history takes the granting of an epoch.' But that time span when Being gives itself to openness can never be found in historically calculated time or with its measures. T h e time span ganted shows itself only to a reflection which is already able to glimpse the history of Being, even if this succeeds only in the form of an essential need which soundlessly and without consequences shakes everything true and real to the roots.

 

3 . In a conference Heidegger amended the original Zeit (time) in the German text to read Epoche (epoch).

 

 Overcoming Metaphysics

 

OvercomingMerap/IY~~ic.c

 

FOUR

 

[The text contains notes on the overcoming of metaphysics from the years 1936 to 1946. Their major part was selected as a contribution to the Festschrift for Emil Pretorius; one section (XXVI) appeared in the Barlachheft of the state theater at Darmstadt 1951 (editor: Egon Vietta). "Overcoming Metaphysics" from the volume Vortrage und Auf satze was added to this book at the request of Martin Heidegger.]

 

in which Being itself is overcome. Above all, overcoming does not mean thrusting aside a discipline from the field of philosophical deducation." "Metaphysics" is already thought as the destiny of the truth of beings, that is, of beingness, as a still hidden but distinctive Appropriating, namely the oblivion of Being. Since overcoming is meant as a product of philosophy, the more adequate rubric might be: the past of metaphysics. Of course this calls forth new erroneous opinions. T h e past means here: to perish and enter what has been. In that metaphysics perishes, it is past. T h e past does not exclude, but rather includes, the fact that metaphysics is now for the first time beginning its unconditional rule in beings themselves, and rules as beings in the form, devoid of truth, of what is real and of objects. Experienced in virtue of the dawning of the origin, metaphysics is, however, at the same time past in the sense that it has entered its ending. T h e ending lasts longer than the previous history of metaphysics.

 

What does "overcoming metaphysics" mean? In the thinking of the history of Being, this rubric is used only as an aid for that thinking to be comprehensible at all. In truth, this rubric is the occasion for a great deal of misunderstanding because it doesn't allow experience to reach the ground in virtue of which the history of Being first reveals its essence. This essence is the Appropriating

1. Although Heidegger uses the familiar word Uberwindung for "overcoming," he means it in the sense of the less familiar word Verwindung. When something is overcome in the sense of being iiberwunden, it is defeated and left behind. This is not the sense Heidegger intends here. When something is overcome in the sense of being verwunden, it is, so to speak, incorporated. For example, when one "overcomes" a state of pain, one does not get rid of the pain. One has ceased to be preoccupied with it and has learned to live with it. Thus, to overcome metaphysics would mean to incorporate metaphysics, perhaps with the hope, but not with the certainty, of elevating it to a new reality.

 

Metaphysics cannot be abolished like an opinion. One can by no means leave it behind as a doctrine no longer believed and represented. T h e fact that man as animal rationale, here meant in the sense of the working being, must wander through the desert of the earth's desolation could be a sign that metaphysics occurs in virtue of Being, and the overcoming of metaphysics occurs as the incorporation of Being. For labor (cf. Ernst Junger, Der Arbeiter, 1932) is now reaching the metaphysical rank of the unconditional objectification of everything present which is active in the will to will. If this is so, we may not presume to stand outside of metaphysics because we surmise the ending of metaphysics. For metaphysics overcome in this way does not disappear. It returns transformed, and remains in dominance as the continuing difference of Being and beings. T h e decline of the truth of beings means: T h e openne0-

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphy.

 

beings and only beings loses the previous uniqueness of their au. thoritative claim.

 

T h e still hidden truth of Being is withheld from metaphysical humanity. T h e laboring animal is left to the giddy whirl of its SO that it may tear itself to pieces and annihilate itself in empty nothingness.

 

T h e decline of the truth of beings occurs necessarily, and indeed as the completion of metaphysics. T h e decline occurs through the collapse of the world characterized by metaphysics, and at the same time through the desolation of the earth stemming from metaphysics. Collapse and desolation find their adequate occurrence in the fact that metaphysical man, the animal rationale, gets fixed as the laboring animal. This rigidification confirms the most extreme blindness to the oblivion of Being. But man wills himselfas the volunteer of the will to will, for which all truth becomes that error which it needs in order to be able to guarantee for itself the illusion that the will to will can will nothing other than empty nothingness, in the face of which it asserts itself without being able to know its own completed nullity. Before Being can occur in its primal truth, Being as the will must be broken, the world must be forced to collapse and the earth must be driven to desolation, and man to mere labor. Only after this decline does the abrupt dwelling of the Origin take place for a long span of time. In the decline, everything, that is, beings in the whole of the truth of metaphysics, approaches its end. T h e decline has already taken place. T h e consequences of this occurrence are the events of world history in this century. They are merely the course of what has already ended. Its course is ordered historico-technologically in the sense of the last stage of metaphysics. This order is the last arrangement of what has ended in the illusion of a reality whose effects work in an irresistible way, because they claim to be able to get along without an unconcealment of the essence o Being. They do this so decisively that they need f suspect nothing of such an unconcealment.

 

1

Io

 

1

 

How does metaphysics belong to man's nature? Metaphysically represented, man is constituted with faculties as a being among others. His essence constituted in such a way, his nature, the what and how of his Being, are in themselves metaphysical: animal (sensuousness) and rationale (nonsensuous). Thus confined to what is metaphysical, man is caught in the difference of beings and Being which he never experiences. T h e manner of human representation which is metaphysically characterized finds everywhere only the metaphysically constructed world. Metaphysics belongs to the nature of man. But what is this nature itself? What is metaphysics itself? Who is man himself within this natural metaphysics? Is he only an ego which first thoroughly fixates itself in its egoity through appealing to a thou in the I-thou relationship? For Descartes the ego cogito is what is already represented and produced in all cogitationes, what is present without question, what is indubitable and always standing within knowledge, what is truly certain, what stands firm in advance of everything, namely as that which places everything in relation to itselfand thus "over against" others. T o the object there belongs both the what-constituent of that which stands over against (essentia-possibilitas) and the actual standing of that which stands opposite (existentia). T h e object is the unity of the constancy of what persists. In its standing, persistence is essentially related to the presentation of re-presentation as the guarantee of having-something-in-front-of-oneself. T h e original object is objectively itself. Original objectivity is the "I think," in the sense of the "I perceive" which already presents and has resented itself in advance for everything perceivable. It is the subiectuw- In the

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphysics

 

order of the transcendental genesis of the object, the subject is the first object of ontological representation. Ego cogito is cogito: me cogitare.

 

The modern form of ontology is transcendental philosophy which becomes epistemology. How does such a thing arise in modern metaphysics? In that the beingness of beings is thought as presence for the guarantee of representation. Beingness is now objectivity. The question about objectivity, about the possibility of standing over against (namely, over against guaranteeing, calculating representation) is the question about knowability. But this question is not really meant as the question about the psycho-physical mechanism of the procedure of knowing, but rather about the possibility of the presence of the object in and for knowledge. "Epistemology" is viewing, theoria, in that the on, thought as object, is questioned with regard to objectivity and what makes objectivity possible (he on). How does Kant guarantee the metaphysical element of modern metaphysics through the transcendental manner of questioning? In that truth becomes certainty and thus the beingness (ousia) of beings changes to the objectivity of the perceptio and the cogitatio of consciousness, of knowledge; knowing and knowledge move to the foreground. "Epistemology" and what goes under that name is at bottom metaphysics and ontology which is based on truth as the certainty of guaranteed representation. On the other hand, the interpretation of "epistemology" as the explanation of "knowledge" and as the "theory" of the sciences errs, although this business of guaranteeing is only a consequence of the reinterpretation of Being as objectivity and representedness. "Epistemology" is the title for the increasing, essential power-

 

lessness of modern metaphysics to know its own essence and the ground of that essence. The talk about "metaphysics of knowledgew within the same misunderstanding. In truth, it is a matter of the metaphysics of the object, that is, of beings as object, of the object for a subject. The mere reverse side of the empirical-positivistic misinterpretation of epistemology shows itself in the growing dominance of logistics.

 

1

Io

Io

 

The completion of metaphysics begins with Hegel's metaphysics of absolute knowledge as the Spirit of will. Why is this metaphysics only the beginning of the completion and not the completion itself? Hasn't unconditional certainty come to itself as absolute reality? Is there still a possibility here of self-transcendence? Probably not. But the possibility of unconditional self-examination as the will of life is still not accomplished. The will has not yet appeared as the will to will in its reality which it has prepared. Hence metaphysics is not yet completed with the absolute metaphysics of the Spirit. In spite of the superficial talk about the breakdown of Hegelian philosophy, one thing remains true: Only this philosophy determined reality in the nineteenth century, although not in the external form of a doctrine followed, but rather as metaphysics, as the dominance of beingness in the sense of certainty. The counter movements to this metaphysics belong to it. Ever since Hegel's death (183 I), everything is merely a countermovement, not only in Germany, but also in Europe.

 

It is characteristic for metaphysics that in it existencia is always consistently treated only briefly and as a matter of course, if it is treated at all. (Cf. the inadequate explanation of the postulates of

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY reality in Kant's Critique o Pure Reason.) T h e sole exception is Ari f totle, who thinks out energeia, without this thinking ever being ab to become essential in its originality in the future. T h e transform tion of energeia to actualitas and reality buried everything whit became apparent in energeia. T h e connection between ousia an energeia becomes obscure. Hegel first thinks out existentia, but in h "Logic." Schelling thinks it in the distinction of ground and exi tence. However, this distinction is rooted in subjectivity. A later and confused echo of Being as physis shows itself in tk narrowing down of Being to "Nature." Reason and freedom are contrasted with nature. Because n; ture is what-is, freedom and the ought are not thought as Being. T h opposition of Being and the ought, Being and value, remains. F nally Being itself, too, becomes a mere "value" when the will entel. its most extreme deformation of essence. Value is thought as a condition of the will.

 

Overcoming Metaphysics This fate, which is to be thought in the manner of the history

of Being, is, however, necessary, because Being itself can open out in its truth the difference of Being and beings preserved in itself

 

Io

 

1

 

VIII

 

Metaphysics is in all its forms and historical stages a uniquc but perhaps necessary, fate of the West and the presupposition of its planetary dominance. T h e will of that planetary dominance is now in turn affecting the center of the West. Again, only a will meets the will from this center. T h e development of the unconditional dominance of metaphysics is only at its start. This beginning starts when metaphysics affirms its deformation of essence which is adequate to it, and surrenders its essence to that deformation and fixates it there. Metaphysics is a fate in the strict sense, which is the only sense intended here, that it lets mankind be suspended in the middle of beings as a fundamental trait of Western European history, without the Being of beings ever being able to be experienced and questioned and structured in its truth as the twofoldness of both in term of metaphysics and through metaphysics.

 

only when the difference explicitly takes place. But how can it do this if beings have not first entered the most extreme oblivion of Being, and if at the same time Being has not taken over its unconditional dominance, metaphysically incomprehensible, as the will to which asserts itself at first and uniquely through the sole precedence of beings (of what is objectively real) over Being? Thus what can be distinguished in the difference in a way presents itself, and yet keeps itself hidden in a strange incomprehensibility. Hence the difference itself remains veiled. A sign of this is the metaphysico-technological reaction to pain which at the same time predetermines the interpretation of the essence of pain. Together with the beginning of the completion of metaphysics, the preparation begins, unrecognized and essentially inaccessible to metaphysics, for a first appearance of the twofoldness of Being and beings. In this appearance the first resonance of the truth of Being still conceals itself, taking back into itself the precedence of Being with regard to its dominance.

 

Overcoming metaphysics is thought in the manner of the history of Being. It is the preliminary sign of the primal incorporation of the oblivion of Being. More prior, although also more concealed than the preliminary sign, is what shows itself in that sign. This is Appropriation itself. What looks to the metaphysical way of thinking like the preliminary sign of something else, is taken into account only as the last mere illusion of a more primal opening out. Overcoming is worthy of thought only when we think about incorporation. This perduring thinking still thinks at the same time about overcoming. Such remembrance experiences the unique Appropriating of the expropriating of beings, in which the need of the

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphysics

 

truth of Being, and thus the origination of truth, opens up ar radiates upon human being in the manner of a parting. Overcomir is the delivering over of metaphysics to its truth. At first the overcoming of metaphysics can only be r c in terms of metaphysics itself, so to speak, in the manner ot heightening of itself through itself. In this case the talk about tl metaphysics of metaphysics, which is touched upon in the boc Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, is justified in that it attempts I interpret the Kantian idea from this perspective, which still sten from the mere critique of rationalist metaphysics. However, mol is thus attributed to Kant's thinking than he himself was able LU think within the limits of his philosophy. T h e talk of overcoming metaphysics can also mean that "metaphysics" is the name for the Platonism portrayed in the modern world by the interpretation of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. The reversal of Platonism, according to which for Nietzsche the sensuous becomes the true world and the suprasensuous becomes th untrue world, is thoroughly caught in metaphysics. This kind ( overcoming of metaphysics, which Nietzsche has in mind in th spirit of nineteenth century positivism, is only the final entanglc ment in metaphysics, although in a higher form. It looks as if th "meta," the transcendence to the suprasensuous, were replaced b the persistence in the elemental world of sensuousness, wherea actually the oblivion of Being is only completed and the suprasenst ous is let loose and furthered by the will to power.

 

1

 

is historicism. If one wanted to construct the history of Being in accordance with the historiographical representational thinking cornman today, the dominance of the oblivion of Being's destiny would be confirmed by this mistake in the most blatant way. T h e epoch of completed metaphysics stands before its beginning. T h e will to will forces the calculation and arrangement of everything for itself as the basic forms of appearance, only, however, for the unconditionally protractible guarantee of itself. T h e basic form of appearance in which the will to will arranges and calculates itself in the unhistorical element of the world of completed metaphysics can be stringently called "technology." This name includes all the areas of beings which equip the whole of beings: objectified nature, the business of culture, manufactured politics, and the gloss of ideals overlying everything. Thus "technology" does not signify here the separate areas of the production and equipment of machines. T h e latter of course have a position of power, to be more closely defined, which is grounded in the precedence of matter as the supposedly elemental and primarily objective factor. T h e name "technology" is understood here in such an essential way that its meaning coincides with the term "completed metaphysics." It contains the recollection of techne, which is a fundamental conditon of the essential developent of metaphysics in general. At the same time, the name makes it possible for the planetary factor of the completion of metaphysics and its dominance to be thought without reference to historiographically demonstrable changes in nations and continents.

 

Without being able to know it and without permitting a know] edge about it, the will to will wards off every destiny, whereby w understand by destiny the granting of an openness of the Being o beings. T h e will to will rigidifies everything in lack of destiny. Ths consequence of lack of destiny is the unhistorical. Its characteristit is the dominance of historiography. Historiography's being at a 10s

 

Nietzsche's metaphysics makes apparent the second to the last stage of the will's development of the beingness of beings as the will to will. T h e last stage's failure to appear is grounded in the predominance of "psychology," in the concept of power and force, in life-

 

 Io

 

T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphysics

 

enthusiasm. For this reason this thinking lacks the strictness and carefulness of the concept and the peacefulness of historical reflction. Historiography rules and, thus, apologetics and polemics. Why did Nietzsche's metaphysics lead to a scorn of thinki~ under the banner of "life"? Because no one realized how, according to Nietzsche's doctrine, the representational-calculative (empowering) guarantee of stability is just as essential for "life" as "increase" and escalation. Escalation itself has been taken only in the aspect of the intoxicating (psychologically), but not in the decisive aspect of at the same time giving to the guarantee of stability the true and ever new impulse and the justification for escalation. Hence it is the unconditional rule of calculating reason which belongs to the will to power, and not the fog and confusion of an opaque chaos of life. T h e misled Wagnerian cult imposed an artistic aura on Nietzsche's thinking and its presentation, which, after the process of the scorn of philosophy (that is, Hegel's and Schelling's) through Schopenhauer, and after Schopenhauer's superficial interpretation of Plato and Kant, prepared the last decades of the nineteenth century for an enthusiasm for which the superficial and foggy element of ahistoricality automatically serves as a characteristic of what is true. Behind all this, however, lies the singular incapacity of thinking in terms of the being of metaphysics and recognizing the scope of truth's essential transformation and the historical sense of the awakening predominance of truth as certainty. Behind it, too, lies the incapacity of thinking Nietzsche's metaphysics in its relation to the simple paths of modern metaphysics in terms of this knowledge, instead of making a literary phenomenon out of it which rather overheats our brains than purifies, and makes us pause, and perhaps even frightens us. Finally, Nietzsche's passion for creators betrays the fact that he thinks of the genius and the geniuslike only in a modern way, and at the same time technologically from the viewpoint of accomplishment. T h e two constitutive "values" (truth and art) in the concept of the will to power are only circumscriptions for "technology," in the essential sense of a planning and calculat-

 

ing stabilization as accomplishment, and for the creating of the "creators" who bring a new stimulus to life over and above life as it is, and guarantee the business of culture. All of this remains in the service of the will to power, but it also prevents the will to power's being from entering the clear light of the broad, essential knowing which can only have its origin in the thinking of the history of Being. T h e being of the will to power can only be understood in terms of the will to will. T h e will to will, however, can only be experienced when metaphysics has already entered its transition.

 

NietzJLL,, metaphysics of the will to power is prefigured in the sentence: "The Greek knew and sensed the terrors and horrors of existence: In order to be able to live at all, he had to set u p the radiant dream-creation of Olympus above them." (Socrates and Greek Tragedy, chapter 3, 1871. T h e original version of Birth of Tragedy from the Spirit of Music, Munich, 1933 .) T h e opposition of the "titanic" and the "barbaric," of the "wild" and the "impulsive" is put here on one side, and beautiful, sublime appearance on the other. Although it is not yet clearly thought out and differentiated and seen from a unified perspective, the idea is prefigured here that the "will" needs at thesame time the guarantee of stability and escalation. But the fact that will is will to power still remains concealed. Schopenhauer's doctrine of the will dominates Nietzsche's thinking at first. The preface to the work is written "on Schopenhauer's birthday." With Nietzsche's metaphysics, philosophy is completed. That means: It has gone through the sphere of prefigured possibilities. Completed metaphysics, which is the ground for the planetary manner of thinking, gives the scaffolding for an order of the earth which will supposedly last for a long time. T h e order no longer needs

 

 7

!

THE END OF PHILOSOPHY Overcoming Metapbyst

 

philosophy because philosophy is already its foundation. But with the end of philosophy, thinking is not also at its end, but in transition to another beginning.

 

unthought. It holds itself in a truth which has long since been forgotten and is without ground.

 

IN

Io

 

Io

Io

 

In the notes to the fourth part of Thus spoke Zarathustra, Nietzsche writes (1886): "We are attempting a venture with truth! Perhaps humanity will perish by it! So be it!" (WW XII, p. 307.) An entry written at the time of The Dawn of Day (1880181) reads: "What is new about our present position with regard to philosophy is the conviction which no age has ever yet had: that we do not have the truth. All men of earlier times "had the truthw-even the skeptics." (WW XI, p. 268.) What does ~ i e t z s c h e mean when he speaks now and then of "the truth"? Does he mean "what is true," and does he think this as what truly is, o r as what is valid in all judgments, behavior, and life? What does this mean: to attempt a venture with the truth? Does it mean: to bring the will to power into relation with the eternal recurrence of the same as what truly is? Does this thinking ever get to the question as to wherein the essential being of truth consists and whence the truth of this essential being occurs?

1

 

There can be an object in the sense of ob-ject only w h l l l a~ l k becomes a subject, where the subject becomes the ego and the ego becomes the ego cogito, only where this cogitare is conceived in its essence as the "original synthetic unity of transcendental apperception," only where the apex for "logic" is attained (in truth as the certainty of the "I think"). Here the being of the object first reveals itself in its objectivity. Here it first becomes possible and, as a consequence, unavoidable to understand objectivity itself as "the new true object" and to think it unconditionally.

XVI

 

~

 

XIV

 

H o w does objectivity come to have the character of constituting the essential being of beings as such? One thinks "Being" as objectivity, and then tries to get to "what is in itself." But one only forgets to ask and to say what one means here by "what is" and by "in itself." What "is" Being? May we inquire into "Being" as to what it is? Being remains unquestioned and a matter of course, and thus

 

Subjectivity, object, and reflection belong together. Only when reflection as such is experienced, namely, as the supporting relation to beings, only then can Being be determined as objectivity. T h e experience of reflection as this relation, however, presupposes that the relation to beings is experienced as repraesentatio in general: as re-presentation. But this can become a matter of destiny only when the idea has become perceptio. T h e transformation of truth as correspondence to truth as certainty, in which the adaequatio remains preserved, underlies this change. certainty as self-guaranteeing (willing-onself)is iustititia as the justification of the relation to beings and of their first cause, and thus of the belongingness to beings. Iusti$catio in the sense of the Reformation and Nietzsche's concept of justice as truth are the same thing. Essentially, repraesentatio is grounded in reflexio. For this reason, the being of objectivity as such first becomes evident where the being of thinking is recognized as explicitly brought about as "I

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphysics

 

think something," that is, as reflection.

 

XVII

 

Kant is on the way to thinking the being of reflection in the transcendental, that is, in the ontological sense. This occurs in the form of a hardly noticeable side remark in the Critique of Pure Reason under the title "On the Amphiboly of the Concepts of Reflection." T h e section is a supplement, but it is filled with essential insight and critical dialogue with Leibniz, and thus with all previous metaphysics, as Kant himself sees it and as it is grounded in its ontological constitution in egoity.

 

find the pure dominance of "egoity" which must be thought metaphysically, and which has nothing to do with naively thought "solipsism." Philosophy in the age of completed metaphysics is anthropology (cf. Holzwege, p. 91 f.). Whether or not one says "philosophical" anthropology makes no difference. In the meantime philosophy has become anthropology and in this way a prey to the derivatives of metaphysics, that is, of physics in the broadest sense, which includes the physics of life and man, biology and psychology. Having become anthropology, philosophy itself perishes of metaphysics.

XIX

 

XVIII

 

Regarded from the outside, it looks as if egoity were only the retroactive generalization and abstraction of what is egolike from the individual "egos" of man. Descartes above all obviously thinks of his own "ego" as the individual person (res cogitans as substantia Fnita). Kant, on the other hand, thinks "consciousness in general." But Descartes also already thinks his own individual ego in the light of egoity which, however, is not yet explicitly represented. This egoity already appears in the form of the certum, the certainty which is nothing other than the guaranteeing of what is represented for representational thinking. T h e hidden relation to egoity as the certainty of itself and of what is represented is already dominant. T h e individual ego can be experienced as such only in terms of this relation. T h e human ego as the individual self completing itself can only will itself in the light of the relation of the will to will, as yet unknown, to this ego. N o ego is there "in itself," but rather is "in itself" always only as appearing "within itself," that is, as egoity. For this reason, egoity is also present where the individual ego by no means presses forward, where it rather retreats, and society and other communal forms rule. There, too, and precisely there, we

 

T h e will to will presupposes as the condition of its possibility the guarantee of stability (truth) and the possibility of exaggerating drives (art). Accordingly, the will to will arranges even beings as Being. I n the will to will, technology (guarantee of stability) and the unconditional lack of reflection ("experience") first come to dominance. Technology as the highest form of rational consciousness, technologically interpreted, and the lack of reflection as the arranged powerlessness, opaque to itself, to attain a relation to what is worthy of question, belong together: they are the same thing. We are presupposing that why this is so and how it came to this has been experienced and understood. We only want to consider the fact that anthropology is not exhausted by the study of man and by the will to explain everything in terms of man as his expression. Even where nothing is studied, where rather decisions are sought, this occurs in such a manner that one kind of humanity is previously pitted against another, humanity is acknowledged as the original force, just as if it were the first and last element in all beings, and beings and their actual interpretation were only the consequence. Thus the solely decisive question comes to predominance: T o

 

 7

 

Io

 

THE END OF PHII,OSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphy.

 

what form does man belong? "Form" is thought here in an indefinite metaphysical way, that is, Platonically as what is and first determines all tradition and development, itself, however, remaining independent of this. This anticipatory acknowledgment of "man" leads to searching for Being first of all and only in man's environment, and to regarding man himself as human stability, as the actual m on to the idea. e

 

~

 

In that the will to power attains its most extreme, unconditional guarantee, it is the sole criterion that guarantees everything, and thus what is correct. T h e correctness of the will to will is the unconditional and complete guaranteeing of itself. What is in accordance with its will is correct and in order, because the will to will itself is the only order. In this self-guaranteeing of the will to will, the primal being of truth is lost. T h e correctness of the will to will is what is absolutely untrue. T h e correctness of the untrue has its own irresistibility in the scope of the will to will. But the correctness of the untrue which remains concealed as such is at the same time the most uncanny thing that can occur in the distortion of the being of truth. What is correct masters what is true and sets truth aside. T h e will to unconditional guaranteeing first causes ubiquitous uncertainty to appear.

 

tional investigation of means, grounds, hindrances, the miscalculating exchange and plotting of goals, deceptiveness and maneuvers, the inquisitorial, as a consequence of which the will to will is distrustful and devious toward itself, and thinks of nothing else than the guaranteeing of itself as power itself. T h e aimlessness, indeed the essential aimlessness of the unconditional will to will, is the completion of the being of will which was incipient in Kant's concept of practical reason as pure will. Pure will wills itself, and as the will is Being. Viewed from the perspective of content, pure will and its law are thus formal. Pure will is the sole content for itself as form.

XXII

 

XXI

 

T h e will is in itself already the accomplishment of striving as the realization of what is striven for. What is striven for is explicitly known and consciously posited in the concept, that is, as something represented in general. Consciousness belongs to the will. T h e will to will is the highest and unconditional consciousness of the calculating self-guaranteeing of calculation (cf. The Will to Power, no. 458). Hence there belongs to it the ubiquitous, continual, uncondi-

 

In virtue of the fact that the will is sometimes personified in individual "men of will," it looks as if the will to will were the radiation of these persons. T h e opinion arises that the human will is the or$in of the will to will, whereas man is willed by the will to will without experiencing the essence of this willing. In that man is what is thus willed and what is posited in the will to will, "the will" is also of necessity addressed in its essence and released as the instance of truth. T h e question is whether the individuals and communities are in virtue of this will, or whether they still deal and barter with this will or even against it without knowing that they are already outwitted by it. T h e uniqueness of Being shows itself in the will to will, too, which only admits one direction in which to will. T h e uniformity of the world of the will to will stems from this, a uniformity which is as far removed from the simplicity of what is original, as deformation of essence from essence, although the former belongs to the latter.

XXIII

 

Because the will to will absolutely denies every goal and only admits goals as means to outwit itself willfully and to make room

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphysics

 

for this game; because, however, the will to will nevertheless may not appear as the anarchy of catastrophes that it really is, if it wants to assert itself in beings; it still must legitimate itself. T h e will to will invents here the talk about "mission." Mission is not thought with regard to anything original and its preservation, but rather a< the goal which is assigned from the standpoint of "fate," thus justi fying the will to will.

 

XXIV

 

T h e essence of the history of Being of nihilism is the abandonment of Being in that in it there occurs the self-release of Being into machination. This release takes man into unconditional service. ~t is by no means a decline and something "negative" in any kind of sense. Hence not just any kind of humanity is suited to bring about unconditional nihilism in a historical manner. Hence a struggle is even necessary about the decision as to which kind of humanity is capable of the unconditional completion of nihilism.

XXVI

 

T h e struggle between those who are in power and those who want to come to power: O n every side there is the struggle for power. Everywhere power itself is what is determinative. Through this struggle for power, the being of power is posited in the being of its unconditional dominance by both sides. At the same time, however, one thing is still covered up here: the fact that this struggle is in the service of power and is willed by it. Power has overpowered these struggles in advance. T h e will to will alone empowers these struggles. Power, however, overpowers various kinds of humanity in such a way that it expropriates from man the possibility of ever escaping from the oblivion of Being on such paths. This struggle is of necessity planetary and as such undecidable in its being because it has nothing to decide, since it remains excluded from all differentiation, from the difference (of Being from beings), and thus from truth. Through its own force it is driven out into what is without destiny: into the abandonment of Being.

 

xxv

T h e pain which must first be experienced and borne out to the end is the insight and the knowledge that lack of need is the highest and most hidden need which first necessitates in virtue of the most distant distance. Lack of need consists in believing that one has reality and what is real in one's grip and knows what truth is, without needing to know in what truth presences.

 

T h e signs of the ultimate abandonment of Being are the cries about "ideas" and "values," the indiscriminate back and forth of the proclamation of "deeds," and the indispensability of "spirit." All of this is atready hitched into the armament mechanism of the plan. T h e plan itself is determined by the vacuum of the abandonment of Being within which the consumption of beings for the manufacturing of technology, to which culture also belongs, is the only way out for man who is engrossed with still saving subjectivity in superhumanity. Subhumanity and superhumanity are the same thing. They belong together, just as the "below" of animality and the "above" of the ratio are indissolubly coupled in correspondence in the metaphysical animal rationale. Sub- and superhumanity are to be thought here metaphysically, not as moral value judgments. T h e consumption of beings is as such and in its course determined by armament in the metaphysical sense, through which man makes himself the "master" of what is "elemental." T h e consumption includes the ordered use of beings which become the opportunity and the material for feats and their escalation. This use is employed for the utility of armaments. In that in the unconditionality of escalation and of self-guaranteeing armament runs out and in truth has aimlessness as its aim, the using is a using up. T h e "world wars" and their character of "totality" are already a consequence of the abandonment of Being. They press toward a

 

 Io

 

THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphysics

 

guarantee of the stability of a constant .form of using things up. Man, who no longer conceals his character of being the most important raw material, is also drawn into this process. Man is the "most important raw material" because he remains the subject of all consumption. H e does this in such a way that he lets his will be unconditionally equated with this process, and thus at the same time become the "object" of the abandonment of Being. T h e world wars are the antecedent form of the removal of the difference between war and peace. This removal is necessary since the "world" has become an unworld as a consequence of the abandonment of beings by Being's truth. For "world" in the sense of the history of Being (cf. Being and Time)means the nonobjective presencing of the truth of Being for man in that man is essentially delivered over to Being. In the age of the exclusive power of power, that is, of the unconditional pressing of beings toward being used u p in consumption, the world has become an unworld in that Being does presence, but without really reigning. As what is real, beings are real. There are effects everywhere, and nowhere is there a worlding of the world and yet, although forgotten, there is still Being. Beyond war and peace, there is the mere erring of the consumption of beings in the plan's self-guaranteeing in terms of the vacuum of the abandonment of Being. Changed into their deformation of essence, "war" and "peace" are taken up into erring, and disappear into the mere course of the escalating manufacture of what can be manufactured, because they have become unrecognizable with regard to any distinction. T h e question of when there will be peace cannot be answered not because the duration of war is unfathomable, but rather because the question already asks about something which no longer exists, since war is no longer anything which could terminate in peace. War has become a distortion of the consumption of beings which is continued in peace. Contending with a long war is only the already outdated form in which what is new about the age of consumption is acknowledged. This long war in its length slowly eventuated not in a peace of the traditional kind, but rather in a condition in which

 

warlike characteristics are no longer experienced as such at all and peaceful characteristics have become meaningless and without content. Erring knows no truth of Being. Instead, it develops the cornpletely equipped plan and certainty of all plans whatsoever i n every area. In the encompassment (circle) of areas, the particular realms of human equipment necessarily become "sectors"; the "sector" of poetry, the "sector" of culture are also only the areas, guaranteed according to plan, of actual "leadership" along with others. The moral outrage of those who d o not yet know what is going on is often Gmed at the arbitrariness and the claim to dominance of the "leadersv-the most fatal form of continual valuation. T h e leader is the source of anger who cannot escape the persecution of anger which they only appear to enact, since they are not the acting ones. One believes that the leaders had presumed everything of their own accord in the blind rage of a selfish egotism and arranged everything in accordance with their own will. In truth, however, they are the necessary consequence of the fact that beings have entered the way of erring in which the vacuum expands which requires a single order and guarantee of beings. Herein the necessity of "leadership," that is, the planning calculation of the guarantee of the whole of beings, is required. For this purpose such men must be organized and equipped who serve leadership. T h e "leaders" are the decisive suppliers who oversee all the sectors of the consumption of beings because they understand the whole of those sectors and thus master erring in its calculability. T h e manner of understanding is the ability to calculate which has totally released itself in advance into the demands of the constantly increasing guarantee of plans in the service of the nearest possibilities of plans. T h e adjustment of all possible strivings to the whole of planning and guaranteeing is called "instinct." T h e word here designates the "intellect" which transcends the limited understanding that only calculates in terms of what lies closest. Nothing which must go into the calculation of the miscalculating of individual "sectors" as a "factor" escapes the "intellectualism" of this intellect. Instinct is the superescalation to

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphysics

 

the unconditional miscalculation of everything. It corresponds to superhumanity. Since this miscalculation absolutely dominates the will, there does not seem to be anything more besides the will than the safety of the mere drive for calculation, for which calculation is above all the first calculative rule. Until now, "instinct" was supposed to be a prerogative of the animal which seeks and follows what is useful and harmful to it in its life sphere, and strives for nothing beyond that. T h e assurance of animal instinct corresponds to the blind entanglement in its sphere of use. T h e complete release of subhumanity corresponds to the conditionless empowering of superhumanity. T h e drive of animality and the ratio of humanity become identical. T h e fact that instinct is required for superhumanity as a characteristic means that, understood metaphysically, subhumanity belongs to superhumanity, but in such a way that precisely the animal element is thoroughly subjugated in each of its forms to calculation and planning (health plans, breeding). Since man is the most important raw material, one can reckon with the fact that some day factories will be built for the artificial breeding of human material, based on present-day chemical research. T h e research of the chemist Kuhn, who was awarded the Goethe prize of the city of Frankfurt, already opens up the possibility of directing the breeding of male and female organisms according to plan and need. T h e way in which artificial insemination is handled corresponds with stark consistency to the way in which literature is handled in the sector of "culture". (Let us not flee because of antiquated prudery to distinctions that no longer exist. T h e need for human material underlies the same regulation of preparing for ordered mobilization as the need for entertaining books and poems, for whose production the poet is no more important than the bookbinder's apprentice, who helps bind the poems for the printer by, for example, bringing the covers for binding from the storage room.) T h e consumption of all materials, including the raw material "man," for the unconditioned possibility of the production of every-

 

thing is determined in a concealed way by the complete emptiness in which beings, the materials of what is real, are suspended. This emptiness has to be filled up. But since the emptiness of Being can never be filled up by the fullness of beings, especially when this . emptiness can never be experienced as such, the only way to escape it is incessantly to arrange beings in the constant possibility of being ordered as the form of guaranteeing aimless activity. Viewed in this way, technology is the organization of a lack, since it is related to the em I : tiness of Being contrary to its knowledge. Everywhere where there are not enough beings-and it is increasingly everywhere and always not enough for the will to will escalating itself -technology has to jump in, create a substitute, and consume the raw materials. But in truth the "substitute" and the mass production of ersatz things is not a temporary device, but the only possible form in which the will to will, the "all-inclusive" guarantee of the planning of order, keeps itself going and can thus be "itself" as the "subject" of everything. T h e increase in the number of masses of human beings is done explicitly by plan so that the opportunity will never run out for claiming more "room to live" for the large masses whose size then again requires correspondingly higher masses of human beings for their arrangement. This circularity of consumption for the sake of consumption is the sole procedure which distinctively characterizes the history of a world which has become an unworld. "Leader natures" are those who allow themselves to be put in the service of this procedure as its directive organs on account of their assured instincts. They are the first employees within the course of business of the unconditional consumption of beings in the service of the guarantee of the vacuum of the abandonment of Being. This course of business of the consumption of beings in virtue of the unknowing defense against unexperienced Being excludes in advance the distinctions between nations and countries as still being essential determinative factors. Just as the distinction between war and peace has become untenable, the distinction between "national" and "international" has also collapsed. Whoever

 

 THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

 

Overcoming Metaphysics

 

thinks in "a European way" today, no longer allows himself to be exposed to the reproach of being an "internationalist." But he is also no longer a nationalist, since he thinks no less about the well-being of the other nations than about his own. Nor does the uniformity of the course of history of our present age consist in a supplementary assimilation of older political systems to the latest ones. Uniformity is not the consequence, but the ground of the warlike disputes of individual intendants of the decisive leadership within the consumption of beings for the sake of securing order. T h e uniformity of beings arising from the emptiness of the abandonment of Being, in which it is only a matter of the calculable security of its order which it subjugates to the will to will, also conditions everywhere in advance of all national differences the uniformity of leadership, for which all forms of government are only one instrument of leadership among others. Since reality consists in the uniformity of calculable reckoning, man, too, must enter monotonous uniformity in order to keep u p with what is real. A man without a uni-form today already gives the impression of being something unreal which no longer belongs. Beings, which alone are admitted to the will to will, expand in a lack of differentiation which is only masked by a procedure and arrangement which stands under the "principle of production." This seems to have as a consequence an order of rank; whereas in truth it has as its determining ground the lack of rank, since the goal of production is everywhere only the uniform vacuity of the consumption of all work in the security of order. T h e lack of differentiation, which erupts glaringly from this principle, is by no means the same as the mere leveling down, which is only the disintegration of previous orders of rank. T h e lack of differentiation of total consumption arises from a "positive" refusal of an order of rank in accordance with the guardianship of the emptiness of all goal-positing. This lack of differentiation bears witness to the already guaranteed constancy of the unworld of the abandonment of Being. T h e

 

earth appears as the unworld of erring. It is the erring star in the manner of the history of Being.

XXVII

 

Shepherds live invisibly and outside of the desert of the desolated earth, which is only supposed to be of use for the guarantee of the dominance of man whose effects are limited to judging whether something is important o r unimportant for life. As the will to will, this life demands in advance that all knowledge move in the manner of guaranteeing calculation and valuation. T h e unnoticeable law of the earth preserves the earth in the sufficiency of the emerging and perishing of all things in the allotted sphere of the possible which everything follows, and yet nothing knows. T h e birch tree never oversteps its possibility. T h e colony of bees dwells in its possibility. It is first the will which arranges itself everywhere in technology that devours the earth in the exhaustion and consumption and change of what is artificial. Technology drives the earth beyond the developed sphere of its possibility into such things which are no longer a possibility and are thus the impossible. T h e fact that technological plans and measures succeed a great deal in inventions and novelties, piling upon each other, by no means yields the proof that the conquests of technology even make the impossible possible. T h e realism and moralism of chronicle history are the last steps of the completed identification of nature and spirit with the being of technology. Nature and spirit are objects of self-consciousness. T h e unconditional dominance of self-consciousness forces both in advance into a uniformity out of which there is metaphysically no escape. It is one thing just to use the earth, another to receive the blessing of the earth and to become at home in the law of this reception in order to shepherd the mystery of Being and watch over the inviolability of the possible.

 

 T H E END OF PHILOSOPFIY

XXVIII

 

N o mere action will change the world, because Being as effectiveness and effecting closes all beings off in the face of Appropriation. Even the immense suffering which surrounds the earth is unable to waken a transformation, because it is only experienced as suffering, as passive, and thus as the opposite state of action, and thus experienced together with action in the same realm of being of the will to will. But the earth remains preserved in the inconspicuous law of the possible which it is. T h e will has forced the impossible as a goal upon the possible. Machination, which orders this compulsion and holds it in dominance, arises from the being of technology, the word here made equivalent to the concept of metaphysics completing itself. T h e unconditional uniformity of all kinds of humanity of the earth under the rule of the will to will makes clear the meaninglessness of human action which has been posited absolutely. T h e desolation of the earth begins as a process which is willed, but not known in its being, and also not knowable at the time when the being of truth defines itself as certainty in which human representational thinking and producing first become sure of themselves. Hegel conceives this moment of the history of metaphysics as the moment in which absolute self-consciousness becomes the principle of thinking. It almost seems as if the being of pain were cut off from man under the dominance of the will, similarly the being of joy. Can the extreme measure of suffering still bring a transformation here? N o transformation comes without an anticipatory escort. But how does an escort draw near unless Appropriation opens out which, calling, needing, envisions human being, that is, sees and in this seeing brings mortals to the path of thinking, poetizing building.

 

 key to the later Hddegger, this condensation of his tho on Bdng is jam-peked-. .Those in the fold will welcome it."

 

Pubblicato da accordo con HarperSanFrancisco, divisione di HarperCollins Publishers, Inc.

La University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 60.637 Copyright 01.973 nella traduzione inglese Harper & Row, Inc. Tutti i diritti riservati. Originariamente pubblicato da Verlag Gunther Neske, Pfullingen, i diritti d'autore 1961 da Gunther Neske Verlag, Pfullinpart del Volume I1 del Che Nietz ~, gen. "Superare Metafisica" è tratto da RF AzIfSatze Vortriige ~, d copyright 1954 da Gunther Neske, Pfullingen. traduzione in inglese da Joan Stambaugh. University of Chicago Press edizione 2003 Stampato negli Stati Uniti d'America 11 10 09 08 07 06 05 2 3 4 5 ISBN: 0-226-32383-8 (Paperback) Library of Congress Catalogare-in-pubblicazione dei dati

la carta utilizzata in questa pubblicazione soddisfa i requisiti minimi di American National Standard di Scienze dell'informazione-permanenza di carta per la stampa dei materiali di biblioteca, ANSI 239,48-1.992.

 

No comments: